Langbahn Team – Weltmeisterschaft

Ernst Laas

Ernst Laas
Era19th-century Philosophey
RegionGermany
SchoolPositivism
InstitutionsUniversity of Strasbourg
Thesis
  • Eudaimonia Aristotelis in ethicis principium quid velit et valeat. [The Principle of Aristotle’s Eudaimonia and Its Significance in Ethics.]
Doctoral advisorAdolf Friedrich Trendelenburg.
Doctoral studentsBenno Kerry, Paul Natorp, Hans Vaihinger, Wilhelm Halbfass.
LanguageGerman
Main interests
epistemology, positivism, history of philosophy, Kantianism, idealism, Aristotle, Plato, pedagogy.
Notable ideas
Correlativism. Modernization of Language Education. Protagoras as founder of all sensualist philosophies.
Laas during his tenure at Strasbourg in 1884 at the age of 47, one year before his untimely death.

Ernst Laas (born June 16, 1837, in Fürstenwalde/Spree; died July 25, 1885, in Strasbourg) was a gymnasium teacher, philosopher of positivism and education, and chair of philosophy and pedagogy at the University of Strasbourg. The insights he found in the history of philosophy and philosophies based on sensualism are key aspects of his scholarly work.

Biography

Laas grew up as the son of the master tailor Johann Peter Laas (1807–57) and his wife Berta Ida Flora (1818–52), née Beil, in economically limited circumstances in Fürstenwalde, Brandenburg, Prussia. Ernst’s childhood was marked by various hardships, especially during the difficult years of 1846 and 1847 and the revolutionary period that followed. His father loyally supported the royalists, which led to retribution from the opposing party; they boycotted his work.[1] During this time as a young boy, Ernst and his younger brother had to collect firewood from the heath in his area after school each day to help their parents, who struggled just to provide the most basic food through their hard work. He quickly became acquainted with the seriousness of life and believed his fate was tied to his own personal energy he put into it. Due to his rough years growing up, Paul Kannengiesser has said that Laas "truly earned everything himself."[2] When Ernst completed his education at the local public school and was ready to choose a career, however, he faced the bleak prospect of becoming a waiter, an errand boy, or a tailor’s apprentice. But thanks to the support of the school principal Rector Gaedke, and General von Massow who admired his father’s loyalty to the crown, he was able to attend the Joachimsthal Gymnasium.[1][3]

Former building of the Joachimthal Gymnasium, Berlin-Wilmersdorf, Bundesallee.

Starting Easter 1851, he attended Joachimsthal’s Gymnasium in Berlin, later becoming a boarding student. Upon leaving school, Ernst noted that his personal struggles and experiences, combined with the educational methods used at home, led him to develop a shy and reserved demeanor which others found off-putting.[1] His noble patron died in December 1853, but his heirs continued his charitable efforts until Laas was able to support himself by taking a position as a private tutor.[2] He was eventually able to support himself financially from 1854 to 1856.

Photo of Adolf Friedrich Trendelenburg. Trendelenburg was one of the most important philosophers for Laas' philosophical and pedogeological development.

In October 1856, Laas enrolled at the University of Berlin to study theology at the request of his parents. But soon his interest soon shifted to study philosophy following the advice from Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg along with winning a prize with an essay on Aristotle. Laas’s association with Trendelenburg was a pivotal moment in his intellectual development. He attended Trendelenburg’s philosophical seminars from the time he entered the university until he earned his doctorate. He also enjoyed Trendelenburg’s personal favor and dedicated his first major work to him.[2] Yet it was not Trendelenburg’s unique metaphysical ideas that significantly influenced Laas, but rather his reformative views on the approach to philosophical study as a whole: his historical method.

This direction represents Adolf Trendelenburg’s lasting contribution, and in this regard, Laas was truly his disciple. Laas applied this historical-critical[4] approach not only in philosophy but wherever he aimed to assess the value of existing concepts by connecting them to the past.[2]

Trendelenburg was known for his knowledge of the history of philosophy and taught in his lectures that a philosopher could learn much for their own thinking and about the thinking of others from the history of philosophy.[5] Through this "historical-critical"[4] method, Trendelenburg advocated for a deep, critical study to distill the enduring elements from the works of the past, which should then inform the true philosophical task of the present. Under Trendelenburg’s guidance, Laas' philosophical thinking initially oriented around Aristotle, and in his doctoral dissertation, he adopted a similar method to what Lessing later successfully employed.[1][2][6] That is, Lessing claimed that:

We remain inexperienced children without history. And without the history of the wisdom of the world in particular, which is nothing but the history of error and truth, we will never learn to appreciate the strength of the human intellect; we will forever remain a pompous sophist who, in love with his idiocies, believes that he is sitting in the lap of certainty; we will be exposed hourly to the danger of being deceived by ignorant prattlers who not seldom call new discoveries what we already knew and believed several thousand years ago.[7]

Laas thus following this method aims to critically extract the correct ideas from the judgments of his predecessors; a method that remained a characteristic feature of his entire approach to research. This approach also influenced his endeavor to search into the genesis of his subjects, guiding him in both philosophy and education.[2] Laas even stated that for all human institutions that have evolved from historical life, immersing oneself in their development is the only way to gain a clear understanding of their validity.[2][4]

At Berlin, philosophy and cultural history were the main focuses of his university studies; in the seminars of Boeckh and Haupt, he developed the philological precision that marked his studies of Aristotle and Kant. Among his teachers was also Du Bois-Reymond. It was precisely during this time when the remarkable successes of the natural sciences were increasingly overshadowing philosophical speculation. As the significance of Hegel’s system waned, the esteem for empirical research rose, which Hegel had somewhat dismissed. This was especially true in German philosophy, particularly in the fields of psychology and epistemology where there was a growing interest in identifying and dissecting empirical facts (Tatsachen). These facts were the objects of experience found in the sciences, which many thought would likewise complement the new historical movement on its path to being a science.[2] And so, Laas was always on the lookout for a solid, fertile, naturalistic foundation, which was indeed greatly influenced by this empirical trend.[3]

Thus, alongside his study of history, he delved into natural sciences. To be sure, while he did not conduct independent research in the natural sciences as he did in philosophy, education, and literary history, he nonetheless absorbed the results of scientific research with remarkable energy and gained a clear understanding of its methods.[2] This is demonstrated in his philosophical writings, which show a wide range of citations of the top scientists of Laas' time. He was, in any case, increasingly keen to emphasize the seriousness and sobriety of scientific thinking. The more firmly he grounded himself in this new scientific reality, the more rigorously he analyzed phenomena and immersed himself in their development, and the more he distanced himself from theories that twist away from the facts or try to leap to a “higher” understanding through some intellectual gymnastics.[2]

Laas received his doctorate in philosophy December 5, 1859 with a dissertation on The Principle of Aristotle’s Eudaimonia and Its Significance in Ethics (Eudaimonia Aristotelis in ethicis principium quid velit et valeat). Laas regarded scientific psychology as the sole basis for ethics and praised Aristotle over Kant because Aristotle derived his moral directives from the specific nature of humans. He saw this as a valuable feature of his ideal of happiness, particularly because it could be realized on this earth. Here, then, one can see the beginnings of Laas's dispute with idealist thinking. He esteemed Aristotle's more empirical approach more highly than Plato's abstract suprasensory ethics based on ideas.[2]

In 1860, he became a teacher of German, Greek, Latin, and Hebrew at the renowned Friedrichs-Gymnasium in Berlin and, in 1868, at the Berlin Wilhelm-Gymnasium. In 1861, he married Martha (1839–1919), née Vogeler and had five sons. His first major publication emerged from his teaching experiences—a guide on teaching German essay writing in the first class of the gymnasium which was published in 1868. Around the same time, he was appointed as a senior teacher with the title of professor at Wilhelms-Gymnasium.[3] He published further studies on German instruction in 1870 and 1871, which led to plans for a thorough revision of his first book. However, his appointment as a full professor at the University of Strasbourg in 1872, advocated by Trendelenburg, somewhat disrupted these plans. Nonetheless, he published German Instruction at Higher Educational Institutions in the same year and revised his earlier work on essay writing in 1876. In 1872, he received a full professorship in philosophy at the newly re-established Kaiser Wilhelm University of Strasbourg, a position he held until his death. Additionally, he published The Pedagogy of Johannes Sturm in 1872 and a small treatise on Gymnasium and Realschule in 1875.[1]

University of Strasbourg at the end of the 19th century. This is where Laas became a professor 1872.

He was a well-informed and perceptive literary historian, as evidenced not only by many valuable comments on the essay topics he compiled from this field (found in his book on German essay writing), but also by his excellent study on Herder’s influence on German lyric poetry that was published in Die Grenzboten in 1871. Moreover, he was a top-tier educator and educational writer, an expert on the history of education, a theorist of style, and capable of using elevated, powerfully effective language when he wrote freely.[1] In his lectures, he initially dealt with literary and cultural-historical topics (including Luther, Lessing, Herder, and Goethe) and educational themes. He lectured on pedagogy during the time of Humanism and the Reformation and on educational theories in ancient and modern times. Although his early days as a professor exclusively focused on pedagogy, his lectures always included philosophical elements. That said, in his own field of philosophy, he was thoroughly familiar with every significant work of the past, especially those important in cultural history as well as contemporary studies. Paul Natorp has said that: "it’s hard to name a highly regarded book on a philosophical subject that he hadn’t referenced at some point in a way that shows he didn’t just read it but studied it deeply."[1]

From 1878 onwards, he lectured exclusively on philosophy and continued to further educated himself in mathematics and the natural sciences.[8] His main philosophical works include Kant’s Analogies of Experience in 1876 and Idealism and Positivism, a three-volume series published between 1879 and 1884, among other publications and reviews, where he fought against the philosophies of Plato and Kant with a deep and open disdain. In the last decade of his life, however, Laas turned with increasing interest and an almost passionate involvement to the problems of the social sciences, law, and political theory.

He strove with all his might to closely link philosophy with the empirical sciences. He primarily sought engagement with the rigorous sciences, and, in this, he was aware of his alignment with the goals of the Kantian school.[1] Like them, he saw figures such as Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo, and Newton in the history of philosophy not just as representatives of the true model of the world but also as exemplars of self-reflection in scientific work. He believed that the “theory” of knowledge should above all else closely observe the “main stages of scientific discovery at work.” He acknowledged being inspired in this regard by Kantian thinkers like Whewell and Apelt.[1]

Despite his critical stance towards theology and romanticism, Laas acknowledged the emotional dimensions of Christianity and the moral significance of art.[9] However, he came across as a man without emotion to many. One of his traits was that he was always quite stern and suppressed any emotional qualities about himself to others, however this aspect of his character was not permanent.[3] His friends have noted that he was a very kind man, which would only be shown in very infrequent moments. For Paul Natorp claimed in his obituary for Laas that:

He wasn’t always the stern, harsh man who seemed forcefully to suppress any softer emotions within himself. If you had only known him this way, then it was all the more wonderful to see the deep kindness of his character emerge freely and vividly during those rare, very special moments. He often seemed to hide this side of himself from most people he interacted with, almost as if he were hiding it from himself. It was as if he saw his calling to wrestle on our behalf with all the riddles that can torment the human mind and heart, to confront the demons that haunt our spiritual existence, so that we could find joy and delicately share in all things human—a sacrifice he made for his mission that was not due to any inherent harshness in his nature.[1]

His commitment to intellectual freedom and rigor made him a respected figure among his students and colleagues even as he challenged their views. But simultaneously, he always fostered an environment of critical evaluation and growth for his students. According to Paul Natorp, Laas was above all:

"a teacher—or perhaps more accurately, an educator [Erzieher]. Even in his role as an academic, his influence may have penetrated more deeply through his personality than the specific content of what he taught; he taught us to think for ourselves and not to just reflect on his thoughts. He had no interest in merely attracting followers to his philosophical perspective unless their conviction showed complete independence. This allowed him to maintain not only personal goodwill but also professional respect for former students who later chose their own paths."[1]

One of his students was the Viennese philosopher Benno Kerry (1858–1889) who published his literary remains after his death. According to Kerry, Laas published knowledgeable and detailed studies on the theoretical philosophy of his time, especially on Kant. Nonetheless, he was namely known for his three-volume chief work Idealism and Positivism (1879–1884) in which he advocated for the supremacy of positivism over idealist thinking. For Laas, the facts (Tatsachen) i.e. the objects of his positivism were the representations that people develop about the world either through “precieving” (warnehmen, Laas’s idiosyncratic spelling which he consistently used instead of wahrnehmen) or “feeling” (empfinden). He considered this sensualistic or positivistic approach to be philosophically superior and more productive than the idealistic approach of most of his contemporaries. In contrast to what he believed to be the problem with idealist philosophy, Laas always stressed that any fact he asserted could be verified, addressed, and developed further by anyone who wished to do so.[10]

Laas’s positivist philosophy found much resonance in Strasbourg during his lifetime. But in the end, Laas philosophized independently and wasn't attached to any contemporary German schools of thought or had any followers, though he was in constant exchange of ideas with various thinkers of the 19th century. Nonetheless, his ideas became the source for controversial discussions on epistemology and moral philosophy. Laas, for example, asserted – similar to Hume, Mill, and Spencer, as well as in contrast to proponents of Kantian philosophy – that human reason is not capable of producing ideas and concepts that guarantee the objectivity of our knowledge and moral actions. He always stressed that people are always dependent on what they “perceive” and “feel.”

However, Laas' association with the British Empiricists, French encyclopedists, and positivists was one of the reasons for his neglect given the prevalence of German nationalism. Laas highlights this nationalism at the end of the final volume of Idealism and Positivism:

As sad as it is, it is a fact that nowadays within certain circles one can already prejudice against a doctrine by simply describing it as an import from England or France: it appears both as unoriginal and unpatriotic. And ours unfortunately has affinities with Condillac and the Encyclopedists, with Hume and Mill; and it even names itself after a word from the Frenchman Comte!

This is further demonstrated when, in 1882 the Neo-Kantian Windelband was appointed to Strasbourg. On his view and the administration's of the University of Strasbourg, Laas’s positivist philosophy was a radical relativism or anti-philosophical sophistry that questioned philosophical values, such as objective knowledge and morality that must be shut down:

I go to Strasbourg with the hope of growing with the higher purpose. They expect from me – strictly between us! – the fight against positivism, which threatens to stamp that university with the mark of radicalism. I know difficult circumstances await me there, and I leave peace behind here. But I have something to achieve there – while here now anyone will maintain the tradition.[11]

The concept of relativism in German philosophical discourse emerged not as a neutral descriptive term, but rather as a polemical tool in academic debates. And this contentious history can be traced to Wilhelm Windelband's influential 1884 characterization, where he dismissed relativism as "the philosophy of the jaded person who no longer believes in anything," and thus associating it specifically with urban skepticism and intellectual inconsistency.[12] And so, Windelband saw it as his “missionary task” to reassert traditional German, particularly Kantian and idealistic, philosophy in Strasbourg against Laas. We can see this in a letter Windelband writes in 1883:[13]

Strasbourg can easily become a dead end... On the other hand, it’s still considered a kind of grand prize for us to be called to the Imperial University, and this call is somewhat imperative. Had I declined it, I could have bought myself a permanent grave in Freiburg... there is a mission to fulfill here. Through unfortunate circumstances... at the German Imperial University, philosophy has been taken over by Laas, a second-rate positivist – one of the most unfortunate appointments in academic affairs. And in response to this, it is now the difficult task to establish the great traditions of German philosophy here, which Liebmann didn’t feel capable of handling long-term... This task is incredibly difficult...: the student body in Strasbourg is... completely different from other German universities: a shallow, philistine attitude prevails which will be very difficult to shake up. Still, all of us who live here work not for the present moment, but for the next generation... It is a very, very long journey from Freiburg to here. From the idyll into the frontlines of battle, stepping into harsh, biting winds![14]

Windelband's treatment of Laas and positivism was largely driven by non-philosophical – essentially political – motivations. And it was these political factors that reduced Germany's first notably "positivist" philosopher and noted critic of Neo-Kantian a priori thinking to being remembered merely as a political figure rather than for his philosophical contributions. Moreover, an 1882 report from Strasbourg University's curator revealed political interference in academic appointments.[15] The document, addressed to the State Secretary of Alsace-Lorraine, discussed Wilhelm Windelband's appointment to replace Otto Liebmann as professor of philosophy:

Windelband belongs as a teacher of philosophy to the direction that can be described as conservative and moderate, as it has until now found representation at the local university through Prof. Liebmann in opposition to the direction of Professor Laas, which tends toward the radical side. Riehl is indeed of Catholic confession, but is considered emancipated in his relationship to the church and stands in philosophical questions on the side of the school to which Laas belongs. From both the political and scientific standpoint, it appears advisable not to leave the field exclusively to the latter school at the university, but rather to restore the proven counterweight, which found its support in the person and teaching of Prof. Liebmann, after his departure through a similar force.[15]

The university brought in Windelband to succeed Liebmann, specifically to prevent the establishment of a Laasian school of thought and block it from gaining a foothold in Strasbourg for political and moral reasons. In 1884, Laas without knowing this was going on, nevertheless attacked Windelband’s Kritische oder genetische Methode? in his essay Ueber teleologischen Kriticismus.[16] In the conclusion of the third volume of his trilogy, Laas wrote about the philosophical and political significance of his investigations:

When I placed my philosophical convictions in fundamental opposition to such highly celebrated names as Plato and Kant; when I seemed to declare war on the idealism praised by countless voices; when I set my views in historical connection with the infinitely often pilloried aphorisms of one of the despised Athenian sophists; when I revealed a certain predilection for the almost frivolous skeptic David Hume; when I introduced my own doctrine under the title of positivism: I had to be prepared for all sorts of misunderstandings and dialectical fencing tricks in an age where slogans often have more effect than arguments, where all forms of “intrusions into another field” (μετάβασις εἰς ἄλλο γένος) flourish most luxuriantly which tendentious rhetoric has invented, where one has become accustomed to defending occupied territory with all means of self-love and sophistry.[17]

Yet, he did not regret having strongly emphasized the contrast between idealism and positivism. On the contrary, he considered some life and world views currently represented in the name of idealistic philosophy not just inaccurate but even “dangerous,” indeed “culturally dangerous.”[17]

However as much as I hold certain forms of “idealism” in high regard, I cannot regret having marked the contrast more than my kinship from the outset. Even now I find some of the most praised species of this genus of life and world views not only more or less inaccurate, but also dangerous, culturally dangerous. And the longer I pay attention to the use of the word, especially in Germany, the more clearly I see that it all too often either presents itself as an easy reach grip for those who lack thoughts and knowledge, or whose cause has some rotten spot. Idealism shimmers in all possible colors and can always count on evoking at least a blind feeling of goodwill. So I hope that this may, in fact, contribute to a purer, more adequate knowledge of the matter represented here, even if it not only renounced rhetorical support but even seemed hostile to the idol of national bias.

But due to overwork, he suffered from health issues as early as 1877. Despite this, he completed his three-volume Idealism and Positivism in 1884, and barely rested until he sent off the last manuscript in September of the previous year. But a ten-day stay in the Black Forest was hardly sufficient recovery for him. In November, he became seriously ill with a kidney disease, which was compounded by asthma and insomnia. After a brief resurgence in the winter, his health rapidly declined.[1] He lost consciousness on July 23 and passed away on July 25 at 3:30 p.m.

After his death, Laas’s positivist ideas were no longer discussed. Successors such as Avenarius, Mach, Ostwald, and Ratzenhofer virtually ignored him.[18] That said. Laas was mentioned in Eisler’s Philosophenlexikon[19] and in Meyers Großes Konversations-Lexikon.[20] But in the standard histories of philosophy of the 20th century, there are no detailed presentations of his ideas.

Laas' grave is located in the Cimetière Saint-Gall in Strasbourg-Koenigshoffen (Section 5A-2-8).[21]

Positivist philosophy

1. Historical background

Title page of Kants Analogien der Erfahrung, where Laas gives his a detail presentation of his views on Kant's epistemology.

Since around 1830, positivism, along with the rise of other sciences and the collapse of German Idealism, increasingly played an important role in philosophy.[22] The Neo-Kantians were busy updating and further developing their philosophical role model in line with the latest scientific developments. From their perspective, they contradicted positivist philosophers, for example, by arguing that judgments about facts are not possible without a priori presuppositions. This led to positivist-themed discussions among Neo-Kantians about Kantian ideas. For instance, there was debate over whether the a priori elements – such as Kant’s concepts and categories – should also be considered facts.[23]

Laas regarded positivism as the “solely scientifically justified” philosophy. According to him, It was free from the “arbitrary absolutisms of speculative philosophy,” especially that of Hegel – as P. Jacob Kohn states in his dissertation on Laas’s positivism – and it employed the method of sciences practiced at the time.[24] Therefore, with his three-volume publication Idealism and Positivism, Laas attempted to establish a unified philosophy that also met “ethical” requirements, based on the “solid foundation of experience,” more specifically on the basis of sensory “perception.”[25] For this foundation, he used terms such as facts, sensations, experiences, and memories [Tatsachen, Empfindungen, Erlebnisse, and Erinnerungen].

In the first volume of his trilogy, Laas presented the general foundations of his positivism with interpretations of texts by Plato, Kant, non-Kantian philosophers, and philosophers close to positivism, such as Condillac from the early modern period. He launched a general attack on idealism, including Aristotle, René Descartes, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, and especially Plato as its founder, as well as Kant. His purpose was to provide a remedy for the "discontinuity of philosophy"; that is, its failure to make progress over the centuries and its want of any clear standards.[26] The only way to put an end to this complaint was through a newer, critical method of the history of philosophy. In contrast to the old method, this method is directed not at the past, but “at the most immediate present and its current interests.”[27] This new method was primarily established on a synthesis between Lange’s History of Materialism[28] in the manner that elucidates foundational and general philosophical principles, and J. St. Mill’s tactic of “hand-to-hand fighting” used in the Examination[29] against Sir William Hamilton. It was also rooted in, however, by Leibniz’s and Trendelenburg’s perennial distinctions in the history of philosophy, and August Boeckhs’, Moriz Haupt’s, and especially Trendelenburg’s philology at the University of Berlin. Just as Trendelenburg attempted[30] by distinguishing between the “fundamental” aspects of a philosophy and its “derived” elements, so that "we might yet recognize the inherent organization, structure, and necessity within this diversity,"[26] for:

The rich array of nuances, shades, entanglements, and complications, along with the many inconsistencies of the authors, have made it possible to weave a fabric with just two threads and two basic colors that initially gives the impression of dazzling variety. Yet, upon closer examination, this seemingly intricate web actually breaks down into a few easily discernible main lines.[31]

This new historical method revealed a fundamental dualism throughout the history of philosophy between the standpoints of Plato and Protagoras.[32] And this dualism swayed for centuries in favor of Plato, benefiting his followers at the expense of their opponents. This historical insight therefore led Laas – as the subtitle of Idealism and Positivism implies – to a “critical examination” of this dualism in order to see if idealism’s hegemonic victory was justified. After his critical examination, he concluded that it is now time to demonstrate that “there is no reason to abandon the ground of positivism,”[33] and only through positivism could “philosophy as a science… finally bear philosophical fruit.”[34]

Portrait of August Comte, the founder of modern positivist philosophy.

When Laas referred to "positivism," he aligned with the traditional German interpretation of the term, associating it with Protagoras and the British empiricists rather than Auguste Comte's teachings, toward which he was generally indifferent or critical. More fittingly termed neo-empiricism in English contexts, Laas's theory focused on restricting knowledge to sensory data. It rejected the notion of an autonomous consciousness separate from perceptual content and denied the existence of objects beyond their perceptual interactions, thereby emphasizing the constant variability of perceived objects.[35]

For Laas, positivist philosophy starts from sensory “perceptions” or facts (empirical objects), and rejects statements about non-sensory things along with idealist philosophy which – like Kant, for example – starts from ontological entities such as “reason” and ethical abstracts such as “ought,” which Kant thinks are present in human reason or understanding “before any experience” (a priori). But in contrast to the a priori, idealists only assigned a subordinate role to sensory “perceptions,” “sensations” and “facts.”[36][37]

At first look, Laas observed it might seem as if the “transcendental philosophical turn… is vastly different from the Platonic view.” However, upon closer inspection, an “interesting kinship” emerges. Do not the “laws of understanding… have something of the paradigmatic character of Platonic ideas?” And doesn't the central role of the a priori forms align parallel to the Platonic ideas “towards the presuppositionless One and Good?”[38] Laas linked this idealistic approach to conceptual realism in logic, to a priori deductive rationalism in epistemology, and to both human spontaneous creativity and divine teleology in metaphysics. He viewed idealism as influenced by a mathematical pursuit of absolute knowledge and related it to the concepts of innate ideas and final causes.[35]

Furthermore, Laas stated that idealistic philosophy is not capable of developing proposals that adequately respond to the current state of scientific development. Instead of starting from “facts,” or sensory “perceptions” like other sciences, idealistic philosophers are still constructing systems of suprasensory world knowledge – such as representatives of transcendental philosophy and Hegelian philosophy – intended to justify the certainty of scientific and everyday action. This certainty, as discussions among philosophers of the 19th century demonstrated, was only promised by Kant’s epistemology but has not yet been fulfilled.[39] Laas’s writings Kant’s Analogies of Experience (1876)[40] and Kant’s Role in the History of the Conflict between Faith and Knowledge (Berlin 1882)[41] provide detailed information on this.

Laas saw himself as a successor to the philosophy of David Hume and John Stuart Mill, and he advocated for positivism or sensualism as a desirable common direction for the philosophy of his time. Although he recognized Auguste Comte as a founder of positivism, he found Comte lacking in pressing philosophical issues, such as statements on subject and object.[42] He rejected other ideas of Comte – including his doctrine of science – and distanced himself from Comte’s later religious ideas, which he considered “mystical and romantic.”[43]

1.1 Plato’s Theaetetus.

Bust of Protagoras (490–420 BCE). Laas saw Protagoras as the person who originated the positivist/sensualist tradition of philosophy.

“Man is the measure of all things,” argued Protagoras. Laas thought this statement to be one of the earliest foundations to his own philosophical approach. As the first volume of Idealism and Positivism makes clear, Protagoras is where all sensualist and positivist philosophy begins.[44] But as we only have fragments of Protagoras’s writings, we have to reconstruct his arguments from what remains. But thankfully, Protagoras’s philosophical account of knowledge is discussed quite heavily in Plato’s Theaetetus, where he gives an argument against his philosophy based on pure perception. While Laas thinks Plato gives some strawmans of Protagoras arguments and philosophical positions, as well as what be believes to falsely tying it to Heraclitus’s doctrine of “everything in flux[45] – which led to a debate between his old student Paul Natorp[46] – he nonetheless acknowledges Plato’s philosophical gifts and literary talent.

“Besides instances where Plato appropriately and clearly distinguishes the positions of the young Theaetetus, the sophist Protagoras, and the ‘Ionians,’ there are other places where the opposition is described in such a general and vague manner that it's hard to definitively say who or what is being discussed. The worst part is that relativism and Heraclitism are so interwoven – often transitioning into each other – that the shifting expression, like a reflection of the presumed indeterminate being, allows no definite interpretation, nor even a clear emphasis of the words. […] If it were certain that Protagoras himself supported his relativism with Heraclitian metaphysics, or if this were truly a necessary prerequisite for his views, or if the idealist gained no argumentative advantage from this connection, then we would view these transitions and chiaroscuro effects merely as delightful, intellectually stimulating exercises in presentation. However, the reality is quite the opposite. So, despite our aesthetic enjoyment of the style, both for Protagoras’ sake and for the sake of the argument itself, we feel compelled to first untangle Protagorean subjectivism from its Heraclitian entwinement and consider it on its own.”[47]

In the dialogue Theaetetus, Plato tells us, through the mouth of the mathematician Theaetetus, that Protagoras argued that knowledge equals perception. And so Laas thinks that this Platonic dialogue, which is solely focused on experiential epistemology and at the same time tries to prove it false, gives the original roots of the principals which he counts as the basis for his positivist philosophy in its earliest and strongest form. But more importantly, Laas thinks this articulation of positivist philosophy has not deviated much from the modern version, while albeit widely misunderstood by the idealist in his day.

“While the sensualism described by Plato (and Aristotle) may still be underdeveloped and lacking in detail, some of its most characteristic features are already so clearly defined that the subsequent work on this principle – since the revival of Epicureanism by Gassendi, especially by the English nominalists and empiricists – has hardly shown any significant deviations in its core essence. It is acknowledged that the origin and foundation of both our thoughts and imaginative creations, as well as scientific truth and certainty, lie in sensory perception, in what is "given" to us. All intellectual development relies on the "abilities" of memory, reproduction, and comparison (and abstraction)… these ideas, shared by all sensualists, including the moderns, are clearly and distinctly articulated, suggesting that even if Plato, who expressed these ideas but turned away to his ‘idealism’ (and ‘rationalism’), had known the more detailed explanations and deeper justifications of today, he would not have been persuaded to change his views. Thus, his idealistic critique and response remain significant up to the present day.”[48]

1.1.1. Protagoras’s argument for sensualism.

Laas attempts to give a reconstruction of Plato’s argument of Protagoras’ sensualism in order to show how the underlying principles originated for his own philosophy. The reconstruction goes like this.[49]

  • (1) Everything that we know and cognize is ultimately based on a passive state of the “soul” which is called sensation or perception.
  • (2) The soul is either a body or its sensations must be regarded as physiologically, organically mediated: this latter conviction is Plato’s belief (Cf. Theaet. 156b; Phileb. 31a f., 42a-e; 44a f., 51a-e; Rep, 583a f.; Tim. 64a f.).
  • (3) There is nothing more certain than perception; the being that it presents here and now is immediately evidential; Plato too does not deny this latter point (Theaet. 152c: “Perception, then, is always of what is, and unerring—as befits knowledge”).
  • (4) The process of sensation begins with an organism’s birth; humans, in their essence, are not distinct from other animals. Even plants have sensations.
  • (5) There are differences of value among the senses; the sense of sight is theoretically the most valuable of all the senses; Plato likewise holds it in high regard.
  • (6) Like seal imprints in wax, memories of perceptions are preserved: depending on their organization, they vary in number and degrees of accuracy and reliability (Theaet. 191c ff.).
  • (7) When we see or hear something, we remember something else that we do not perceive right away, but which has a connection or similarity with that thing, especially if it is particularly close to our interests.
  • (8) From the remnants of memories arise representations; then from representations arise reflections and comparisons; from reflections and comparisons: thus arise judgments, beliefs, expectations which can both be true and false.
  • (9) With time, practical experience and routine are formed through consolidated attention of what habitually happens: we thus learn to interpret distant objects correctly; we in advance take account the pleasurable and unpleasurable consequences of our actions; we learn to deal with external things and people, as much as is humanly possible in accordance with our will.
  • (10) The sharper and more accurate one’s observations, and the more reliable their memory, then the more one is in a position to predict what will come about with the objects of perception by virtue of the rules which factually govern all coexistence and succession; those who can do so enjoy great prestige.

Thus ultimately, if science takes shape as pure perception and experience, then it is nothing more than justified true belief.[49]

Bust of Plato (427–348 BCE). Laas took Plato to be the founder of the idealist tradition of philosophy.

Laas thinks this argument, given by Plato’s reconstruction of Protagoras’s sensualist philosophy, exhibits the original principles of all empirical or positivist philosophy. “In this respect, the doctrine of modern sensualism aligns completely with that which Plato confronted.”[50] And he thinks that it is highly likely that if Plato were among us in modern times, “he would maintain his [idealistic] stance.” Because of this, he thinks modern proponents of positivist or sensualist philosophy have not deviated from these principals, even though some progress has been made. (E.g., Laas thinks this was done with David Hume and John Stuart Mill).

1.1.2 Plato's argument against sensualism.

Likewise, Laas’s gives a summary of his reconstruction of Plato’s argument that a science [episteme/Wissenschaft] – like philosophy – could never be based on pure perception as Protagoras claimed.[51] For science or knowledge [episteme/Erkenntniss] are distinctly higher, more sublime, purer, and more spiritually enlightened than perception, which is influenced and shaped by experience. But humans capable of science or knowledge possess unique qualities not found in animals; they have an active, spontaneous mind and reason, not derived from passive states or mediated physically through perceptions generated by experience like other animals are. This is because human reason contains pre-existential, original knowledge in the form of intellectual concepts or “ideas” that transcend ordinary sensory experiences and give access to a supernatural reality. Likewise, the process of knowing these “ideas” is fundamentally a “recollection” of these intellectual concepts that are latent from birth, awaiting active rediscovery within oneself. Since true knowledge requires the human soul or mind to increasingly ignore the sensory input from the body; the mind must aim to become “pure” and free from sensory contamination to grasp pure objects with pure thoughts. Philosophy (dialectic) represents the purest form of this knowledge-seeking, free of sensory influence, where progress is made from ideas to ideas. Mathematics serves as a preliminary stage to this, as it abstracts from sensuality and orients the soul toward pure thinking and truth. Although sensory experiences may prompt reflection, they are mainly useful in pointing out contradictions that need to be resolved intellectually, not perceptually. True knowledge comes from an active recollection and contemplation of these a priori ideas, which are fundamentally separate from the passive, animalistic, and physically mediated state of perception. Thus, science or knowledge are not perception because it involves a distinct, higher form of cognitive activity that engages intellectual concepts, which are pre-existential and not derived from sensory experiences.[51]

With that said, Laas thought the impact of Plato’s argument in the Theaetetus against anti-sensory philosophy was too severe and pervasive, shaping our thoughts and cultural significantly for the worse.[52] For one, Laas critiques the development of Platonism for not maintaining a consistent, scientific progression, as he notes that its initial developments led to excesses in asceticism and mysticism, which in the end diluted its philosophical richness. Secondly, Laas argued that modern Platonists often focus selectively on Plato’s doctrines, while rarely seeking to revitalize the entire philosophical framework. For this reason, Laas tried to point out a tendency within Platonism: it drifts towards non-scientific realms of myths and pious intuitions, while simultaneously blurring the lines between serious philosophical inquiry and mere images.[53]

Building on this, Laas discusses how Descartes and Leibniz adapted and modified Platonic thought. On the one hand, Descartes emphasized the “natural light” of reason as a criterion for truth, thereby defining humans as thinking substances with innate ideas while separating the human mind from the body. Leibniz, on the other hand, took idealist philosophy further by merging Platonic and Cartesian elements, which in the end advocated for a sophisticated rationalism that recognized innate ideas as inherent properties of the human soul, setting the stage for Kant’s critical examination of rationalism in response to empiricism. As a result, Kant sought to redefine the boundaries of “pure reason,” thereby limiting its domain to the field of possible experience and establishing a priori knowledge as foundational to human cognition. Laas thought that Kant’s philosophy represented a significant shift in idealism: the transcendental shift. For Kant argued for a form of a priori knowledge and principles as essential to understanding, which Laas thought reflected Plato’s influence yet also marking a departure into new philosophical territory.

1.2 The 5 motifs of idealism.

Laas, in his attempt to argue against idealism, identified five motifs that idealist philosophy utilized in order to attack sensualism/positivism to support their standpoint through out Western history.[54] These are:

  1. The Mathematical, Scholastic Aspect (Aristotle, Spinoza, Kant). This is the exaggerated appreciation and premature, inappropriate imitation of the pattern of strictly chained (syllogistic) reasoning given by mathematics.[55] This “consists in the belief that real science in general is only that which proceeds like mathematics, and the corollaries resulting from this belief: (1) that “deduction” and systematization must be carried out at all times and as soon as possible, (2) that where such a procedure is inapplicable, there is no ground for genuine science in general,  (3) that ontological concepts admit of systematization just as strict as mathematical ones: (4) to which was attached the naïve and fatal presupposition that such “concepts” could simply be taken up from the manner of expression of a national language, without the necessity of engaging in historical investigation and critical reflection on the real genesis and on the plasticity and ambiguity of such terms.”[56]
  2. The Inclination Towards the Absolute (Aristotle, Wolff, Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Rousseau). Platonism is characterized by the endeavor to trace all scientific knowledge back to absolute principles or even to a single principle whose further justification would be neither possible nor necessary. Laas calls this the urge towards the unconditional or the absolute. Plato’s idea of the Good, Aristotle’s certain principles of being that are first in nature and ultimate for us, form such an unconditioned, presuppositionless principle. The degree of approximation to these principles is also regarded as the degree their ability to count as science. Evidence of such an endeavor is also seen in the endeavor of the followers of Wolff to derive Leibniz's principle of sufficient reason from the principle of identity.
  3. The Assumption of Normative Laws of Reason (Descartes, Leibniz, Wolff, Crusius, Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, Herbart, Lotze, Hamilton). The conviction that there are normative laws for our actions as well as for being which have their roots elsewhere than in our senses and the given According to Laas, this view has dominated the philosophical thought of different times and nations more than any other component of Platonism.[57] Laas also calls this the rationalist or aprioristic motif.
  4. The Motif of Spontaneity (Aristotle, Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Kant, Fichte, Hegel). The assumption that our perceptions, feelings, and the "residues of memory" they settle into are merely passive states of consciousness accompanied by physiological processes, but that alongside these passive states of consciousness there is some kind of pure activity which takes place from within our higher self found in the intellect. This spontaneity is thought to be the specific characteristic that distinguishes humans from animals. It is solely humans who are able to spontaneously trigger theoretical these acts of thought of their own accord through this power within. Thus Laas believes, in contrast to given facts, idealists posit that humans possess some non-animalistic capacity or faculty i.e. something beyond given sense- perception, that has a power or potential to actively or spontaneously through something called “reason,” “mind,” “intellect,” “ideas,” from which all thinking and knowing derive their origin and validity. Therefore, this “power” not only has the power and authority to judge before all experience about all “possible experience,” but also it is to extend beyond the domain of the perceived, even the perceivable with ontological statements. For instance, the spontaneity motif is seen in Descartes, for whom the mind in its pure essence is an original activity, pure, clear and determined, recognizing the truth. It then shows an even further development in Kant, above all in his pure reason, which has exclusive independence is the source of ideas and in this shows such pronounced spontaneity that humans thereby go far beyond everything that sensibility can only provide them with. This motif then reaches the climax of its development in Fichte and Hegel.
  5. The Transcendent or Suprasensible Motif (Kant). The longing belief that every spiritual principle that thinks and knows and whose forms and laws are in accordance with knowable being is entitled to a home and purpose other than this earth; that our world of perception and a life that ends with death “points towards a supernatural and suprasensible world of higher value and to a life beyond.”

2. Sensualistic positivism

By professing anti-Platonism, Laas does not want to defend everything that could fall under it,[58] but only what he calls positivism. Positivism is namely:

that philosophy which recognizes no other foundations than positive facts, that is, outer and inner perceptions; which demands of every belief that it prove the facts, the experiences, on which the belief rests.[59]

Thus “the positivist… is at the same time a sensualist.”[60] Sensualism is an approach for the explanation of phenomenon within our conscious life that begins with the given. In Laas' own words:

The sensualist fundamental claim [is that] that all higher mental processes and states, including even thinking, “knowing,” that is, “reason,” are to be grasped as lawfully “transformed” perceptions and lived experiences of feeling, needing, memory-endowed, spontaneously moving beings (animalia), [and for this claim] no more than facts are taken into account. Nowhere does the sensualist reach out to contents and processes that cannot be experienced, that cannot be scientifically constituted. And to no extent does the sensualist claim that they have already succeeded in what they are striving for with their “explanations”; that the sensualist has already truly grasped all supposedly particular differentiations of consciousness as gradual ones: the sensualist thus holds for the time being to the fact which surely does not speak against them, and that up to now both “thinking” and all higher mental functions in the course of time have only ever been encountered as something subsequent, as something behind original perception, behind animalistic desire [animalischem Begehren].[61]

In short, Laas fundamentally viewed the possibilities of philosophy differently than the idealists Plato and Kant. The latter had claimed that every person possesses a mental faculty called reason whereas wants to begin epistemology and ethics with solely with what we experience and perceive. According to Laas, historically speaking, Kant had merely replaced the previous scholastic metaphysics with a different term. Sensualists or positivists deny entities such as God and reason, and assert that all thinking, judging, and representations are fundamentally based on “sensory sensations” or “perceptions” or “facts.” For Laas, contrary to all experience, idealists claim that the faculty of “reason” determines thought and action and can judge everything, even what a person has not yet experienced.

Moreover, positivists think sensually and base their arguments exclusively on the sensibly experienceable, on facts [Tatsachen]. These facts, unlike the “non-sensible” transcendental categories and Platonic ideas, are the empirical objects that are accessible to everyone which stimulate independent thinking and action. The sensibly experienceable, or the world of matter and the natural sciences, can be sufficiently explained through mutually conditioning factors. As Hume had made clear, it is questionable to construct causal connections and habitually hold them to be “true.”[62]

From an idealistic perspective, it is objected that the sensibly experienceable does not serve as a suitable basis for investigation because it continuously changes. This applies also to psychic phenomena, or our “perception,” thinking, judging, feeling. Everything is in flux, as Heraclitus is said to have noted. This statement prompted Plato to invent eternal, unchanging ideas. Kant, spurred by Hume’s skepticism, claimed a priori concepts free from experience to create certainty.[63] For this reason, Laas concludes that both philosophers have left people with a faithful trust in their idealistic assertions, instead of advising them to verify these claims based on facts.[64]

For a positivist, “change” or “transformation” is an empirical fact that philosophy must accept and investigate if it aims to provide scientific guidelines for thinking and acting. Laas thought that the development of science in the 19th century shows that despite all change and transformation, and despite all errors, there are useful research results. But idealistic claims of absoluteness ignore this.[65] According to Laas, from our “perceptions,” memories and representations emerge, that is, “psychic realities” with which we can conduct scientific research.[66]

Laas also counted among the changes in the world the changes or variations in “perceptions.” People do not only perceive facts differently individually. Even what is supposedly the same is perceived differently at different times. Laas thought this is one of the strongest and most universally understandable objections to idealism, which assumes that there are ideas or a reason within humans that enable consistent knowledge. Similarly Johann Ulrich from Jena criticized this, one of the first and well-known interpreters of Kant and a contemporary of Kant. Protagoras expressed this everyday experience or fact with his statement that “Man is the measure of all things.” Plato, interpreting Protagoras, added in Theaetetus 160c the idea: “Things are for me as they are for me, and for you as they are for you.”[67]

But for Laas, if the entirely individual perspective of each person were a correct fact, then any idealistic attempt would become unnecessary – whether through any kind of doctrine of ideas or even more sophisticated transcendental philosophical constructions – to transform “perceptions” into something objective. He will show on the following “pages” that although something similar could succeed in positivism, it would be in a completely different way than usual.[68]

Laas, keen to avoid the pitfalls of "monstrous" subjective idealism, along with "skepticism," "frivolity," and "trivial common sense philosophy," started to lean towards a neo-Kantian perspective by advocating for an ideal or complete consciousness.[1][35] Because, by echoing Mill’s assertion that the aggregate of actual sensory objects falls short in constructing a coherent world, Laas argued that the world encompasses all conceivable contents of perception, guaranteed to an ideal consciousness, which philosophy aims to reconstruct.[35] He asserted that while objects (facts) are independent of consciousness (albeit not perception), this includes the ideal consciousness, thus preserving the feasibility of scientifically investigating the physical world. This approach was meant to guard against "skepticism," despite acknowledging the world's relative and fluctuating nature.

At the end of the first volume of his historical-critical analysis in Idealism and Positivism, Laas’s described his positivism as an idealism “entirely of this world.” The ideas [Ideen] he uses, however, are self-made and have their roots in sensory perceptions. They do not come from pure reason or the Platonic realm of ideas, but rather from very practical desires and human needs for improving society.[69]

3. Correlativism.

The term correlativism [Korrelativismus] has disappeared from philosophical discussion for more than 100 years. The fundamental meaning associated with it is found in the correlation of measurement variables and functions in mathematics and statistics.

For Laas, correlativism means the intertwined relationship between subject and object in perception. This theory subscribes to three core ideas. Firstly, that perceptions are the result of pairs of interconnected, dynamic processes that are constantly in flux. Secondly, because of this continual change, perceptions themselves lack permanence and are always in a state of “becoming.”[70] Lastly, all perceptions exhibit an inseparable connection between the subject (the perceiver) and the object (the perceived), such that neither can exist without the other.

While Laas “won’t discuss the Protagorean origin of the first two ideas,”[70] he believes that “we can attribute the third to the sophist.” This third idea is framed as a significant milestone in the development of sensualism, as it “represents an insight of fundamental and far-reaching importance,”[71] and “if it first arose in Protagoras’ mind, this brilliant ‘sophist’ deserves more respect in the history of philosophy than he has received,” regardless of the historical accuracy of Plato’s accounts, since they sometimes portray Protagoras in a critical light.

Likewise for Laas, correlativism distinctly rejects the notions of subjectivism and idealism that were put forward by philosophers like Descartes, Berkeley, and Kant, where they argued against this idea that perceptions are merely subjective experiences or modifications of consciousness. Instead, Laas presents correlativism as a theory of “subject-objectivism,” where the existence of objective perceptual content is inherently tied to a perceiving subject, and vice versa.

This is because, for Laas, the perceptual world is not produced by the “I,” or any synonymous terms like subject, consciousness, mind, intellect, etc. Perceptions are not a spontaneous creation or reaction of the inner self, for “to be a perceiving subject without perceiving something is impossible. In other words, consciousness, soul, or self, apart from sensory perception, is nothing.”[72] Moreover, perceptual objects (what we see, hear, etc.) are not subjective modifications or states of consciousness; they are the most original and independent forms of objects, distinct from states of consciousness. Consciousness cannot exist without perceptual content, and perceptual content always implies the presence of a perceiving subject. The subject (the perceiver) and the object (the perceived) are inseparably linked.

Thus correlativism:

“repeats the old idea that nature is an appearance, but not in the ancient natural-philosophical sense, nor in the Platonic or Kant-Herbartian sense, and without the accompanying notions that such a meaning suggests: without the tendency to understand the ‘essence’ or ‘principle’ behind the appearance that ‘manifests’ in it, and without the assumption that appearance points to something that appears. No, appearance is not taken in this sense at all. Rather, nature is an appearance because it only has a relative meaning; it is only conceivable as an object for a perceiving, thinking self. And this self, as mentioned, does not exist without a non-self, that is, without perceptual objects.”[73]

3.1. Event rather than substance

Similar to Hume,” Laas sees “in the ‘world’ nothing more than a collection of sensory or perceptual realities and possibilities.” Beyond these realities, there is for him “no object ‘in itself’ and no transcendent ‘matter.’”[74] On the other hand, for idealists like metaphysicians and rationalists, the world consists of two substances, namely “matter” and “mind.”[75] Laas considers only “subjective states (feelings) and sensory content (sensations).”[76] Similarly, this is done by the anti-metaphysicians Richard Avenarius and Ernst Mach after him.

Contrary to Kantian philosophy, humans do not need “transcendental forms of intuition” for the concept of an extended world. The representation of extension, according to Laas, is acquired from birth through the senses. Thus, everyone can inherently conceive of extension and space, “in terms of the position of his body and his living conditions. These representations never leave them throughout their life.”[77]

3.2. Experience of wholeness

Laas always bases his theory of knowing on physical events, while Kant relies on rational definitions. This accounts for the marked difference between their theories knowing. For Laas, the subject-object relation is “correlative” [correlative/korrelativ] That is, the subject and object are not – as Kant thought – absolute, independent “existences,” but “rather both are correlative phenomena: they are ‘moments’ of an ‘experiential whole.’”[78] Thus, the self has no “transcendent existence.” The self lives “through the actual and conceivable connections of the present moment, the experienced and the experienceable.” Therefore, “the present moment is the most certain; and in the same is always the correlation… of self and world: neither of these moments exists without the other.”[79]

Subject and object together generate “the object of perception, on the one hand, and perception” as a psychological state on the other. The generating processes are in constant flow and have “an existence that varies from moment to moment.”[80] They are “inseparable twins, stand or fall together.” However, Laas states that his theory of knowledge is not “subjectivism anymore, but… subject-objectivism [Subjekt-Objektivismus]; it is, strictly speaking, not relativism, but correlativism.”[81]

With his correlativism, Laas responded to the allegation by the idealistic philosophy of his time, which claimed that positivism was merely “a new edition of egoism or solipsism.” Laas counters that critique with the tools of idealist epistemology, arguing that positivist facts are merely mental representations of consciousness with no connection to the transcendent or transcendental object.[82] Laas refutes this accusation with references to the entirely different framework of his philosophizing—among other things, for him, the separation of mind and body is not phenomenally demonstrable. His focus is on the individual and society, that is, “on the present and its current interests.”[83] For these, mental facts, representations, and “perceptions” that people use are axiomatically indispensable.[84]

One of his interpreters, Dragischa Gjurits, observes: “No matter how we turn it, the fact remains that we can never epistemologically escape from correlativism.”[85] Gjurits further notes that correlativism is the central axis of all of Laas's philosophical views around which they revolve.[86]

4. Epistemology

Title page to Idealismus und Positivismus vol. 3.

In the early modern era, scientists had established epistemology as a fundamental discipline of science. According to Richard Rorty, in Locke’s time, it was an empirical endeavor aimed at justifying the new sciences that had emerged since the Renaissance, “from below” through the senses. Previously, the scholastic schools had justified the sciences “from above,” from God and reason. Epistemology, as Locke conceived it, was meant to be a “natural philosophy”: scientific research should clarify what the human mind can know, judge, and understand.[87]

About 100 years after Locke, Laas thought that the epistemological undertaking in Germany was once again directed by idealistic, Kantian, or post-Kantian ideas. For these idealists, or all “anti-sensualist tendencies” as Laas also called them, all representations, ideas, and actions arise from the intellectual capacity they call reason. Reason guarantees the objective validity of philosophical statements when they are formulated in accordance with correct logical laws in conjunction with a priori concepts. Reason not only enables philosophers but all people to make correct judgments about any possible experience as well as about non-experiential matters.[88]

Laas observes that sensualists like Protagoras, and positivists like himself, consider these idealistic assertions to be unfounded. From his perspective, they are, among other things, a result of the Platonic construct of “absolute certainty” and “innate ideas.” According to the scientific standards of the 19th century, for Laas, this approach should now be considered outdated.[89] In terms of human action and thought, Laas even refers to this idea as a “harmful error” because it ultimately ignores what people perceive. No demand of reason can change the fact that the facts (“perceptions”) are as they are.[90] Positivists, like Berkeley, Locke, and Hume, start from “perceptions” and accept that what people “perceive” is relative and changeable. Unlike idealists, however, positivists maintain that this reality can be scientifically addressed.[91]

4.1. The facts of human knowledge

It is part of every person’s experience to have repeatedly found that the continuity of our “perceptions,” or our thinking, is constantly interrupted. We notice that the impressions of different senses mingle and connect. We experience that memories, fantasies, and fragments of thoughts intervene in every thinking process. Yet, people have always been capable of conducting science because, according to Laas, they have no problem with their "perceptions," judgments, and feelings constantly changing.[92]

In everyday life, people handle their “perceptions,” or changes in facts, in the following tried and tested ways:

  1. They primarily rely on their “perceptions.” Mistakes are easily resolved by further “perceptions.” Other people give us clues about this. Thus, everyone can easily learn to differentiate between real and presumed representations or “perceptions.”
  2. The world shows overall enough constancy for people to adapt to changes through actions. Scientifically fruitful are all distinctions that improve our ability to “navigate the world of diversity,” understand its laws, and make predictions.[93]
  3. Changes do not create confusion; they are accepted as facts.
  4. “Perceptions” of all kinds are related to each other, thus creating a coherent world. Laas explains this fact through correlativity: an objectivity that is created by the coherence of all facts from all people.[94]

4.2. Scientific knowledge

Science picks up all perceptions that are more or less superficial and random or serve only the individual, and then scrutinizes them. By systematically observing, either directly or through the intermediary of the medium, scientists try to “establish scientific fundamental facts.”[95]

Scientists live with probabilities. They must assume that there is no certainty. “They are accustomed to starting with the provisional and progressively searching for the definitive.” For this purpose, they infer law-like changes in their research subjects from changing relations. Under the current scientific conditions, they unify the different individual perspectives into a consistent representation of the specific object.[96] For Laas, this does not affect “formal truth.” It compares things under abstract conditions – for example, using mathematical tools – which are concretely incomparable. Moreover, science can hypothetically or fictitiously dissolve “perceivable” things (e.g., atomic theory).

Private and scientific evaluations of facts are results of “complicated chains of thought.” They are based on arbitrary judgments of taste or on presumed effects. Positivists assess research outcomes according to the highest common utility. However, even they cannot specify what this actually consists of. What benefits everyone must therefore be continuously investigated together.[97]

A Treatise of Human Nature by David Hume, one of the most influential books for Laas.

Scientifically fruitful would also be all distinctions that improve our abilities to “navigate the world of diversity,” understand its laws, and make predictions. Each conceptual differentiation and categorization serves the development of the sciences. The idea of exploring human capabilities – because they are fundamental conditions of all sciences – was also suggested by David Hume in his Treatise on Human Nature to all modern philosophers.[98] The similarity with Hume’s phenomenology of the human mind, particularly of human “perceiving” through “impressions,” is reflected in the epistemology of Laas. The terms and issues used by Laas are not only linguistically related to Hume's sensualist thinking but are likely comparable in substance as well.[99][100]

4.3. The foundations of his epistemology

Laas bases his epistemology exclusively on “sensations.” From these, both from his own perspective and from the viewpoint of other sensualists like Locke, Comte, Hume, and Condillac, representations and facts develop, which guide human orientation.[101] Reason plays a subordinate role for Laas. He considers it – as Hume had phrased – to be “the slave of sensations.” It primarily serves logical thinking. But an epistemology that aids human action is not made possible through reason. From a positivist perspective, “sensations” are fundamental. Neurophysiologically, they are characterized as “physical accompaniments” of knowing [Erkennens].[102]

The terms “sensations,” “perceptions,” and “facts” are used by Laas interchangeably. They do not denote “knowledge” [Erkenntnisse] but rather what precedes and conditions “knowing” throughout life. According to Laas, modern idealistic epistemology, whose main proponent Kant with his transcendental philosophical version of rational idealism that starts from something secondary, namely a genetically later element, is “reason,” and declares it the spiritual “court of justice” [Gerichtshof] that evaluates all knowing.[103]

“Pure reason,” according to Kant, supplies all the means of knowledge, with the subservient participation of sensory events, to recognize the world.[104] However, he overlooks that the world is always present to us through “sensations of temperature, touch, and pressure.”[79] In Laas's view, Kant acted as if the mind were present to consciousness as a “substance”; and as if the self were more present than the constantly present sensations of touch and pressure on our skin.[105] Accordingly, in the first preface of the Critique of Pure Reason (1781/1787), he devalued the “physiology of the human mind” conducted by Locke in his Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690) because Locke had derived it from the “rabble of common experience.”[106]

In 1877, a reviewer of the Jena Literary Gazette[107] recommended to the Kantian adherents of the a priori of his time to confront this “vigorous attack on the transcendental hypothesis.” It might be, the reviewer suggested, that Laas’s critique marks a “turning point in the development of the theory of knowledge, that is currently being worked on so much.”[108] The prevailing theory of knowing seems to have “perceived” this possible “turning point” as a “blind spot” of its own knowledge. For unlike Laas, it insists inappropriately that subject and object are not only separated but that the object must in every respect be an “independent entity.”[109]

5. Positivist ethics

The improvement of society was also the guiding principle of the ethics developed by Laas. It is a religion-free “morality brought down to earth.”[110] He considers it impossible that various religions can contribute to peaceful coexistence. Additionally, matters of faith are not scientifically answerable.[111]

Title page of the second volume of Idealismus und Positivismus.

From his perspective, it is unnecessary for citizens to belong to a religion. Instead, it is essential to guide everyone to act morally. A morality valid for all could only be developed collectively, as individuals would be overwhelmed by this task.[112] His ethics follow the “eudaimonistic” principle.[113] He characterizes this principle with the idea that one can lead a fulfilling life, both individually and together with others. The specifics of this concept for his time, including prospects for possible further developments, are the subject of his “ethics.”

5.1. The exclusion of existing moral concepts

Laas claims that current and past moral concepts lack a philosophically and logically sound foundation and remain stuck in the moral self-evident truths of their respective times. This applies to all views that assume human innate nature enables people to make morally correct decisions and act accordingly, as was the case for Aristotle and philosophers who followed him.[114]

Similar errors among Christian philosophers have led to the assumption of a “purely ideal human” who could act morally correctly if only he wanted to, and therefore could also make morally right decisions for social policy. This applies, for example, to Herder, Fichte, and Schiller. Laas notes that this claim – because of its fundamental ambiguities – is not suitable for community life and carries the potential for inciting unforeseeable social conflicts.[115]

Laas also attests ambiguity to the “instinctive moral concepts” of English thinkers, such as the Platonist Shaftesbury and the Enlightenment philosopher Hutcheson. For Laas, they merely observed that moral judgments “occur with instinctive immediacy.” And so the conditions under which these moral judgments operate remain forever hidden. According to Laas, this means individuals are neither enabled to control their actions nor placed in a position to reflect on them.[115]

Kant's moral approach fails due to the unproven assertion that reason, autonomous and free from immorality and combined with the will, makes ethical action possible.[116] Kant does not clarify how people can be induced to moral actions, except to demand that these be compulsorily made a duty, thereby incorporating Christian beliefs and convictions. He uses terms like “transcendental freedom” and the formal Golden Rule, which express Platonic-Aristotelian views. However, Laas points out that the moral law is founded “in the culturally acquired, in the feelings of solidarity and justice,” and not in the unprovable pure reason.[117]

5.2. Ethics as a wisdom of life.

Laas characterizes his ethics as “practical wisdom for life.” This wisdom “balances the pleasure and utility of the individual with the pleasure and utility of all others in such a way that it produces the highest bliss for the whole.” Thus, Laas describes both the process and the current state of individual and societal ethics. Moral action unfolds human skills and follows maxims that arise from human experience and guarantee collective happiness “with probability.” Corrections are made that, according to human judgment, are likely to improve pleasure and utility. Together, possible consequences of each decision are considered in order to continuously advance the moral action of all people.[118]

5.3. Forerunners to his ethics

Bust of Epicurus, whom Laas sees as his forerunner in ethics in antiquity.

Laas cites the moral theories of the Epicureans and Jeremy Bentham as models for his ethics. According to Laas, the Epicureans laid the groundwork for his positivist ethics. For the Epicureans, ethics is committed to the pleasure of life. It functions socially as “creation of needs” and “agreements of utility” to protect people from harming each other. Thus, morally correct actions are those that protect the individual from harm and benefit society. If moral laws are deficient in this respect, they must be improved.[119]

The most successful further development of Epicurean ethics, Laas claims, was achieved by Jeremy Bentham. He expanded the sympathetic and friendly impulses of the Epicureans into a “universal philanthropy.” This individualized ethics, which Bentham calls “private ethics,” are realized in the context of the development of social policy and legislation.[120] With that said, Laas considers Bentham’s idea that ethically good actions naturally align with the prudently calculated, as if by itself, to be a mistake. Laas thinks that contemporary morality can build on the values and formulations of history. Because in general and in essence, history had the right thing in mind and, in the majority of cases, it indeed was right. But also, in contrast to Bentham, Laas adheres to the concept of duty “You shall!”[121]

"Finally, there is another argument that speaks against the morality of well-understood interest. It has a Kantian tinge, but its core and content are perfectly understandable. All serious duty comes with a categorical: Thou shalt! Who would want to give this formulation to the inspirations of prudence? It will appear as advice, not as a command; it will be hypothetical, not categorical. They will say: If you want to be happy and you find your pleasure in this course of action, more pleasure in this than in that, you will do well, etc. But why they should demand to be happy or to have pleasure in something, they cannot explain in any way. Morality must therefore either stop with its: Thou shalt! or the morality of calculation and prudence is not the true one... The first is claimed by consistent and outspoken egoists. They consider all feelings of duty to be an infatuation or foolishness. For them there is no 'Thou shalt!'... The other is our opinion. We do not believe that the whole of history up to now has been subject to a tremendous aberration, fantasy and self-deception in its moral estimations and formulations; rather, we are firmly convinced that, despite all changes and errors, it has always had the right thing in mind in general and in essence, both in its reasoning and in its detailed determinations, and that in the majority of cases it has also made the right decision. And so we remain attached to the concept of duty and the 'Thou shalt.' Not, of course, in such a way that, in the manner of Platonic morality, we only recognize duties and no rights, or that we want to allow the latter to take a disproportionate back seat to the former. On the contrary, we are inclined to give equal weight to both concepts."[121]

5.4. Ideals of His Ethics

Laas defines morality, or ethics, as the "science of ideals" of his practical wisdom for life. These ideals are the highest good, the highest duty, and the highest virtue.

  1. The highest good is the highest possible absence of pain and the greatest surplus of pleasure for all sentient beings.
  2. The highest human duty is to act in such a way that this good can develop as effectively as possible.
  3. The highest human virtue is a form of character or, more contemporarily expressed, an individual behavior that can produce these ideals as perfectly as possible.
A portrait of Jeremy Bentham by Henry William Pickersgill. Laas sees Bentham's ethics of utility as founding in the modern era the same tradition of ethical thought he is supports.

It is the task of both private and public education to develop this behavior without coercion. The morally valuable aspects, moral duties, and virtues are substantive tasks that people must solve together.[112]

Morality is a social function. According to Laas, it is shaped by the demands of others and the needs of each individual.[122] The starting point for the implementation of his ideals is therefore the respective valid morality or the practiced moral and self-evident behaviors. They must be examined to determine the extent to which they serve both individual and common interests. Moral education must not only be free of violence and coercion, but furthermore, if everyone is to respect moral rights and duties, then everyone must individually also have a say in the matter.[123]

5.5. The objectivity of morality

The designation “objectively valuable” applies only to those values that “lie in the well-understood general interest of a larger number of sentient beings.” This “very simple idea” establishes “the indissoluble unity of duties and rights” and is derived exclusively from human “needs and interests.” For example, a truly objective moral value is the desire of all people to limit the despotism of individuals and groups.[123]

Laas’s definition of “objective” follows his view that subject and object are inseparably connected. He has called this Correlativism [Korrelativismus]. Objectivity in this sense is a functioning, harmonious subject-object relation. Laas also refers to this type of objectivity as “subject-objectivism.” With this, he also clarifies the connection he sees between his notion of objectivity and that of Protagoras. A similar concept can be found in Arthur Schopenhauer, for whom “will” and “representation” provide a mutually enabling foundation for comprehending and forming the world.[124][125]

5.6. Morality needs collaboration.

The moral development of both individuals and society depends on the cooperation of everyone working together. Small, but manageable cooperation provides the initial important impetus for this. The more people come together in a well-organized cooperation and feel solidarity, the greater the average prospect of increasing happiness for individuals. The highest form of cooperation is the entire human race working together, including the animals “trained and bred” in order to meet our needs. Social organizations continuously work on the progressive development of a fulfilling life (eudaimonia) for all. Because of this, they should be supported through the development of social policy techniques: “It is the task of social policy technique to bring to light and implement the legal and duty demarcations necessary to enhance the common good.”[126] Moreover, he denied the identification of self-interest with egoism and held, rather, that self-interest dictates the performance of duties and the fulfillment of demands and expectations imposed on the individual by his environment. In this way, ethical values are the consequences of a particular social order. They acquire validity when they are judged, in the long run and by a considerable number of people, to be worthwhile.[35]

5.7. Morality has history.

The specific goal of the prevailing morality is subject to societal development, which pursues the highest satisfaction “without knowing what enables this satisfaction.” Therefore, the current state of moral culture consists “of attempts to delineate freedoms and necessary duties from each other, so that overall an increase in happiness for many seems attainable.”[127] Only through the course of historical development will people improve their sense of the generally beneficial and their understanding of the best means for achieving it, so that sufferings decrease and joys increase.[128]

Reform of the language educational system

1. Education and cultural development

Laas advocated for thorough reforms of all existing higher educational institutions, especially the gymnasia. He noted that these institutions still clung to the centuries-old, scholastic form of education which believed it could do without any connection to real life and instead practiced the exclusive imparting of theoretical book style knowledge. He published his tested ideas in 1872 in Der deutsche Unterricht auf höheren Lehranstalten. He emphasized that his reform proposals were overdue consequences of changed socio-political conditions. This resulted in a book that he had painfully lacked as a young teacher.[129]

2. Modernization of language education

From Laas's perspective, the outdated curriculum concepts and content arose from the fact that the curricula and syllabuses still valid in his time had already been developed in the 16th century. The reformer Melanchthon had established the contents and methods of teaching to meet the requirements of that era. As a result, Latin remained a subject and the language of instruction, just as it had been in the Middle Ages. At the time, this corresponded to the importance of Latin as the language of science and as the language of communication throughout Europe. These conditions no longer existed in Laas’s time. National languages had replaced Latin in the sciences, social interactions, and literature.

3. The Changing role of Latin in education

But when Laas was alive, the old curricula and syllabuses had not yet been changed. This led to criticism and discontent from many involved in educational instructional design regarding the methods and content used. The outdated curricula primarily prevented the higher educational institutions from evolving into general educational institutions that should serve the learning needs and interests of the people of their time. It was mostly the students who wanted to pursue a teaching career that benefited the most.[130] However, Latin was no longer the language of the scientific and educated world.[131] And so, Laas felt that it was no longer appropriate that students failed their final exams due to a specific number of errors in Latin grammar tests.

4. To interpret instead of imitate

He proposed extensive and, in the discussions of his time, controversial changes: primarily a reduction in grammar and formal style exercises in the classical language subjects. His final suggestion specifically addressed the teaching practice of having students present their own formulated and memorized texts as “speeches” before the class. Laas considered these “speeches” a waste of time due to their low quality of their content and minimal learning incentives.[132] Instead of such formal content, the focus should primarily be on the substantive interpretation of ancient writers, including texts by contemporary German-speaking authors. This way, students could also learn to write genuinely independent texts. Likewise, Laas was focused on the personal development of the students, which was not adequately fostered under the existing curricula.[133] He had already elaborated on this idea in 1868 in Der deutsche Aufsatz in der ersten Gymnasialklasse (Prima.) and supplemented it with additional material and resources.

Influence

Photo of Paul Natorp.

One of his most influential students was the Neo-Kantian philosopher Paul Natorp. Natorp wrote in his obituary for Laas that his approach to education – emphasizing independence over imitation – left a lasting impact on his students and the philosophical community.[1] Natorp became a student and worked with Laas on achieving a coherent version of positivism when he went to Strasburg in mid 1870s. But Natorp ended up eventually going against his positivism. “Just when I thought I had grasped the ‘consistency’ of positivism that we had long sought together, it then appeared to me as an illusion. And so from that point on, the historical progression from Hume to Kant now seemed justifiable to me.” In the end, despite the rigorous mentorship, differences in philosophical outlook eventually led to the cessation of a long-standing collaboration with the fellow philosopher, described by Laas in a letter to Natorp as a divergence of “natural destiny.”

“Everyone follows the path dictated by their original intellectual constitution; it’s good to try for a long time to understand and benefit from even contrary thoughts; and you have followed this path with self-denying perseverance for a long time, but I believe it is now better for you to continue developing along the proper course of your natural destiny.”[1]

Laas then pointed Natorp towards the Kantians from whom he believed he would gain more support than from him. Natorp's move away from positivism struck Laas as “almost elegiac.”[1] He overcame that “elegiac mood” through reflection which best characterizes the spirit in which he worked: “education towards independence is more dignified than training imitators.”[1] Nonetheless, Natorp credits Laas with inspiring his commitment for the essential integration of historical and specialized research within philosophy. In fact, Natorp views himself as both a disciple of Laas and an adherent of Hermann Cohen's perspectives, finding joy in the synthesis of these influences.[1] Likewise, Natorp believed he and Laas were more similar in thinking then what Laas believed:

"Moreover, the gap between his beliefs and mine seems smaller to me than it appeared to him, and how it probably had to appear given his way of thinking. Unlike what Laas believed, I wasn’t his student with self-denying perseverance but a student with joyful conviction, and I have remained so in more than one respect up until today."[1]

Laas's historical-philosophical method advocates for a methodical examination of the origins and development of philosophy as a science, using scientific viewpoints and philosophical theories to uncover underlying systematic laws (for Laas these laws are psycho-genetically developed).[134] This approach seeks to reveal the inherent order within what might initially appear as chaotic philosophical progressions. Characterized by Natorp as a form of "constructing" history, this method is therefore based on the premise that understanding the "syntax" of a science prevents its history from appearing disjointed.[1][135][30]

Works

His chief educational works were Der deutsche Aufsatz in den ersten Gymnasialklassen (1868), and Der deutsche Unterricht auf höhern Lehranstalten (1872; 2nd ed. 1886). He contributed largely to the Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie (1880–82); the Literarischer Nachlass, a posthumous collection, was published at Vienna (1887).[136] None of Laas work’s have been translated into English.

Here is a list of his works taken from Paul Kannengiesser’s obituary for Laas and some additional texts Kannengiesser missed.[137]

1. Philosophical and Historical Writings.

Books and Articles.

(1859) “Eudaimonia Aristotelis in ethicis principium quid velit et valeat.” [“The Principle of Aristotle’s Eudaimonia and Its Significance in Ethics.”] PhD diss. University of Berlin. Digitized.

(1863) Aristotelische Textesstudien. [Studies in Aristotelian Texts (Concerns the first four books of Physics)]. Programm des Friedrichs-Gymnasiums, Berlin: Gustav Lange. Digitized.

(1876) Kants Analogien der Erfahrung. Eine kritische Studie über die Grundlagen der theoretischen Philosophie. [Kant’s Analogies of Experience. A critical Study of the Foundations of Theoretical Philosophy] Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. Digitized.

(1879) Idealismus und Positivismus. Eine kritische Auseinandersetzung. Erster, allgemeiner und grundlegender Teil. [Idealism and Positivism. A Critical Examination. First, General and Foundational Part] Vol. 1, Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. Digitized.

(1880) “Die Causalität des Ich.” [“The Causality of the I.”] In: Viertel Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, edited by Richard Avenarius, pp. 1–54; 185–224; 311–367, Leipzig: Fues’s Verlag (R. Reisland). Digitized.

(1881/1882) “Vergeltung und Zurechnung.” [“Retribution and Imputation.”] In: Viertel Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, edited by Richard Avenarius. 1881: pp. 137–185; 296–348; 448–489; 1882: pp. 189–233; 295–329. Leipzig: Fues’s Verlag (R. Reisland). Digitized: 1881; 1882.

(1882) Idealismus und Positivismus. Zweiter Teil: Idealistische und positivistische Ethik. [Idealism and Positivism. Part Two: Idealist and Positivist Ethics] Vol. 2, Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. Digitized.

(1882). Kants Stellung in der Geschichte des Konflikts zwischen Glauben und Wissen. Eine Studie. [Kant’s Position in the History of the Conflict Between Faith and Knowledge. A Study.] Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. Digitized.

(1883). “Aphorismen über Staat und Kirche.” [“Aphorisms on Church and State.”] In: Viertel Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, edited by Richard Avenarius, pp. 1–16, Leipzig: Fues’s Verlag (R. Reisland). Digitized.

(1883). “Zur Frauenfrage.” [“On the Women Question.”] In: Deutsche Zeit- und Streitfragen. Jahrgang, edited by Franz von Holzendorff, vol. 12. no. 184. pp. 297–332, Berlin: Carl Habel. Digitized.

(1883). “Lambert, Johann Heinrich.” In Allgemeine Deutsche Biographie, 1st ed., 17:552–56. Allgemeine Deutsche Biographie 1875–1912. München/Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot. Digitized 1 and 2.

(1884). “Über teleologischen Kriticismus.” [“On Teleological Criticism.”] In: Viertel Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, edited by Richard Avenarius, pp. 1–17, Leipzig: Fues’s Verlag (R. Reisland). Digitized.

(1884). “Neuere Untersuchungen über Protagoras.” [“Recent Investigations into Protagoras”] In: Viertel Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, edited by Richard Avenarius, pp. 479–497, Leipzig: Fues’s Verlag (R. Reisland). Digitized.

(1884). Idealismus und Positivismus. Dritter Teil: Idealistische und positivistische Erkenntnistheorie. [Idealism and Positivism. Part Three: Idealist and Positivist Epistemology.] vol. 3, Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung, 1884. Digitized.

(1884). “Einige Bemerkungen zur Transcendentalphilosophie.” [“Some Remarks on Transcendental Philosophy.”] In: Strassburger Abhandlungen zur Philosophie. Eduard Zeller zu seinem siebenzigsten Geburtstage, edited by Paul Siebeck, 61–84, Freiburg and Tübingen: Akademische Verlagsbuchhandlung, 1884. Digitized.

(1887) Literarischer Nachlass. [Unpublished Literary Remains] Edited by Benno Kerry, Vienna: Deutschen Worte, 1887. Digitized.

  • ———. 1887. “Idealistische und positivistische Ethik [Idealistic and Positivistic Ethics].” In Literarischer Nachlass [Unpublished Literary Remains], edited by Benno Kerry, 1st ed., 13–32. Vienna: Deutschen Worte. Digitized.

Book advertisements and reviews

(1874) Review of G. Teichmüller’s “Ueber die Unsterblichkeit der Seele.” In: Philosophische Monatshefte, edited by F. Ascherson, J. Bergmann, and E. Bratuscheck, vol. 10. no. 3. pp. 111–134, Berlin: F. Henschel. Digitized.

(1879) “Selbstanzeigen für Idealismus und Positivismus. Eine kritische Auseinandersetzung. Erster, allgemeiner und grundlegender Theil.” In: Viertel Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, edited by Richard Avenarius, pp. 503–504, Leipzig: Fues’s Verlag (R. Reisland). Digitized.

(1880) Review of A. Netter’s “De l'intuition dans des découvertes et inventions, ses rapports avec le positivisme et le Darwinisme.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 3, p. 92, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1880) Review of J. H. Witte’s “Die Philosophie unserer Dichterheroen. Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte des deutschen Realismus. I Band: Lessing und Herder.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 13, p. 445, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1881) Review of H. Girard’s “La philosophie scientifique. Science, art et philosophie. Mathématiques, sciences physiques et naturelles, sciences sociales, art de la guerre.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 9, pp. 316–318, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1881) Review of “G. W. Leibniz Philosophische Schriften. Herausg. von C. J. Gerhardt. IV Band.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 17, pp. 659–660, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1881) Review of G. Biedermann’s “Philosophie als Begriffswissenschaft. I Teil. Die Wissenschaft des Geistes.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 26, pp. 1035–1036, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1881) Review of M. J. Gaufrès’s “Claude Baduel et la Réforme des Études au XVIe siècle. Ouvrage couronné par l'académie de Nîmes.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 38, pp. 1467–1468, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1882) Review of H. Brocher’s “Les révolutions du droit, Études historiques destinées à faciliter l'intelligence des instructions sociales. Tome II: L'enfantement du droit par la guerre.” In: Göttinger Gelehrte Anzeigen. Unter er Aufsicht der Königl. Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften, no. 46, pp. 1456–1466, Göttingen: Dieterich’sche Verlags-Buchhandlung. Digitized.

(1882) Review of Rudolf Eucken's “Zur Erinnerung an K. G. F. Krause. Festrede gehalten zu Eisenberg am 100. Geburtstage des Philosophen.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 4, pp. 124–125, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1882) Review of G. M. Schultzky’s “Das Quadrat der Bildung. Mathematisch-philosophische Erwägungen. Mit einer lithogr. Taf.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 16, pp. 563–564, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1882) Review of Georg Voigt’s “Friedrich Rückerts Gedankenlyrik nach ihrem philosophischen Inhalte dargestellt.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 20, p. 708, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1882) Review of James Sully’s “Illusions, a psychological Study.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 23, pp. 819, Berlin: Weidmannsche,. Digitized.

(1882) Review of Johann Heinrich Loewe’s “Lehrbuch der Logik.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 31, pp. 1107–1108, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1882) Review of Karl Christ. Friedr. Krause’s “Vorlesungen über Aesthetik oder über die Philosophie des Schönen und der schönen Kunst. Aus dem handschriftlichen Nachlasse des Verfassers herausg. von Paul Hohlfeld und Aug. Wünsche. Angehängt: 3 Dresdener Vorlesungen, ein Brieffragment und eine Abhandlung über Schönheit und 3 Tafeln über die Gliedbauverschiedenheit der poetischen Schönheit, die Kunst und die Baukunst.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 40, pp. 1411–1412, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1882) Review of Hugo Sommer’s “Ueber das Wesen und die Bedeutung der menschlichen Freiheit und deren moderne Widersacher.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 43, pp. 1525–1526, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1882) Review of “Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz philosophische Schriften. Herausg. von C. J. Gerhardt. V Bd.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 45, pp. 1603–1604, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1882) Review of Joh. Friedr. Herbarts’s “Sämmtliche Werke. In chronologischer Reihenfolge herausg. von Karl Kehrbach. I Bd. Mit einer lithograph. Taf.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 51, pp. 1819–1820, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1882) Review of Herm. Rehberg’s “Die Principien der monistischen Naturreligion. Moderne Anschauungen über Religionsreformen.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 52, p. 1851, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1883) Review of Hugo Ginsberg’s “Spinozae opera philosophica. Mit Einleitungen herausg. Vol I–IV.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 8, pp. 261–262, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1883) Review of Theodor von Varnbüler’s “Die Lehre vom Sein.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 29, p. 1027, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1883) Review of Georg von Giżycki’s “Grundzüge der Moral. Gekrönte Preisschrift.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 32, pp. 1122–1123, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1883) Review of Edw. Caird’s “Hegel.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 34, pp. 1187–1188, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1883) Review of Karl Uphues’s “Grundlehren er Logik.” In: Viertel Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, edited by Richard Avenarius, pp. 231–247, Leipzig: Fues’s Verlag (R. Reisland). Digitized.

(1884) Review of F. Schmidt-Warneck’s “Die Sociologie Fichtes.” In: Göttinger Gelehrte Anzeigen. Unter er Aufsicht der Königl. Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften, no. 22, pp. 889–893, Göttingen: Dieterich’sche Verlags-Buchhandlung. Digitized.

(1884) Review of Friedr. Ueberwegs’s “Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie. III Teil. Die Neuzeit. 6. mit einem Philosophien- und Litteratoren-Register versehene Aufl. Bearb. und herausg. von Max Heinze.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 2, pp. 43–44, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1884) Review of Louis Philbert’s “Le Rire. Essai littéraire, moral et psychologique.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 16, p. 572, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1884) Review of Franz Staudinger’s “Noumena. Die »transcendentalene Grundgedanken« und die »Widerlegung des Idealismus«.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 36, pp. 1300–1301, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1884) Review of Raph. Koeber’s “Das philosophische System Eduard von Hartmanns.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 41, pp. 1500–1501, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1885) Review of Élie Rabier’s “Leçons de philosophie. I. Psychologie.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 7, pp. 217–218, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

2. Writings on pedagogy and literary history.

Books and articles.

(1868/1877). Der deutsche Aufsatz in der ersten Gymnasialklasse (Prima). Ein Handbuch für Lehrer und Schüler, enthaltend Theorie und Materialien, zusammengestellt aus den Erträgen und Erfahrungen des Unterrichts. [The German Essay in the First Grammar School Class (Prima). A Handbook for Teachers and Students, Containing Theory and Materials, Compiled from the Results and Experiences of Teaching.] Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. Second print 1874. Second, revised edition: Der deutsche Aufsatz in den oberen Gymnasialklassen. Theorie und Materialien. Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung, 1877. 1st edition; 2nd edition.

(1870). “Der deutsche Unterricht auf höheren Lehranstalten.” [“German Instruction in Upper Secondary Schools.”] In: Zeitschrift für das Gymnasialwesen, edited by H. Bonitz, R. Jacobs, P. Buhle, no. 24, pp. 177–243; 625–662; 705–752, Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. Digitized.

(1871). “Zum deutschen Unterricht.” [“On German Instruction.”] In: Zeitschrift für das Gymnasialwesen, edited by H. Bonitz, R. Jacobs, P. Buhle, no. 24, pp. 561–629; 848–852, Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. Digitized.

(1871). “Goethe und das Elsass.” [“Goethe and Alsace.”] In: Die Grenzboten, vol. 1, no. 30, pp. 13–18; 44–50, Leipzig: Friedrich Ludwig Herbig. Digitized.

(1871). “Herders Einwirkung auf die deutsche Lyrik.” [“Herder's Influence on German Poetry.”] In: Die Grenzboten, vol. 2, no. 30, pp. 534–548; 577–584; 609–618; 654–662, Leipzig: Friedrich Ludwig Herbig. Digitized.

(1872). Der deutsche Unterricht auf höheren Lehranstalten. Ein kritisch-organisatorischer Versuch. [German Instruction in Higher Secondary Schools. A Critical and Organizational Essay.] Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. Digitized.

(1872). Die Pädagogik des Johannes Sturm historisch und kritisch beleuchtet. [A Historical and Critical Look at the Pedagogy of Johannes Sturm.] Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. Digitized.

(1875). “Gymnasium und Realschule. Alte Fragen mit Rücksicht auf das bevorstehende Preussische Unterrichtsgesetz historisch und kritisch von Neuem beleuchtet.” [“Gymnasium and Realschule. Old Questions with Regard to the Upcoming Prussian Teaching Law Examined Historically and Critically from a New Perspective.”] In: Deutsche Zeit- und Streitfragen. Jahrgang, edited by Franz von Holzendorff and W. Oncken, vol. 4. no. 49–50. pp. 1–96, Berlin: Carl Habel. Digitized.

Book advertisements and reviews

(1860). Review of Heinrich Viehoff’s “Vorschule der Dichtkunst, theoretisch-praktische Anleitung zum deutschen Vers- und Strophenbau mit vielen Aufgaben und beigegebenen Lösungen.” In: Archiv für das Studium der neueren Sprachen und Literaturen, edited by Ludwig Herrig. no. 28 pp. 296–304, Braunschweig: George Westermann. Digitized

(1860). Review of H. Kurz’s “Leitfaden zur Geschichte der deutschen Literatur.” In: Archiv für das Studium der neueren Sprachen und Literaturen, edited by Ludwig Herrig. no. 28 pp. 308–312, Braunschweig: George Westermann. Digitized.

(1861). Review of “Bändchen von den Erläuterungen zu den deutschen Klassikern. Nos. 19. 22. 23.” In: Archiv für das Studium der neueren Sprachen und Literaturen, edited by Ludwig Herrig, no. 29 pp. 299–303, Braunschweig: George Westermann. Digitized.

(1862). Review of Wilhelm von Humboldt's "Aesthetische Versuche über Goethe's Hermann und Dorothea. Dritte Auflage. Mit einem Vorwort von Hermann Hettner.” In: Archiv für das Studium der neueren Sprachen und Literaturen, edited by Ludwig Herrig. no. 31 pp. 198–202, Braunschweig: George Westermann. Digitized.

(1862). Review of Theodor Kind’s “Anthologie neugriechischer Volkslieder im Original mit deutscher Uebersetzung.” In: Archiv für das Studium der neueren Sprachen und Literaturen, edited by Ludwig Herrig. no. 31 pp. 206–213, Braunschweig: George Westermann. Digitized.

(1862). Review of “Klopstock's Oden, erläutert von Heinrich Düntzer. 6 Hefte.” In: Archiv für das Studium der neueren Sprachen und Literaturen, edited by Ludwig Herrig. no. 32 pp. 223–224, Braunschweig: George Westermann. Digitized.

(1862). Review of Chr. von Bomhard’s “Dreissig Themata zu Aufsätzen für die höheren Unterrichtsanstahen.” In: Archiv für das Studium der neueren Sprachen und Literaturen, edited by Ludwig Herrig. no. 32 pp. 224–225, Braunschweig: George Westermann. Digitized.

(1862). Review of Moritz Müller’s “Zu Göthe's Geburtstag! Ein Gedenkblättchen, Freunden und Gesinnungsgenossen gewidmet.” In: Archiv für das Studium der neueren Sprachen und Literaturen, edited by Ludwig Herrig. no. 32 p. 225, Braunschweig: George Westermann. Digitized.

(1862). “Noch ein Wort zu Düntzer's Erläuterungen.” In: Archiv für das Studium der neueren Sprachen und Literaturen, edited by Ludwig Herrig. no. 32 p. 452–456, Braunschweig: George Westermann. Digitized.

(1883) Review of O. Apelt’s “Der deutsche Aufsatz in der Prima des Gymnasiums. Ein historisch-kritischer Versuch.” In: Zeitschrift für das Gymnasialwesen, edited by H. Kern and H. J. Müller, no. 37, pp. 672–679, Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. Digitized.

(1883) Review of Otto Willmann’s “Didaktik als Bildungslehre nach ihren Beziehungen zur Socialforschung und zur Geschichte der Bildung. I Bd. Einleitung. Die geschichtlichen Typen des Bildungswesens.” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 1, pp. 5–6, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

(1884) Review of G. Wendt’s “Aufgaben zu deutschen Aufsätzen aus dem Altertum.” In: Zeitschrift für das Gymnasialwesen, edited by H. Kern and H. J. Müller, no. 38, pp. 689–694, Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. Digitized.

(1884) Review of Alexander Bain’s “Practical essays” In: Deutsche Litteraturzeitung, edited by Max Roediger, no. 44, pp. 1612–1613, Berlin: Weidmannsche. Digitized.

Notes

  1. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t Natorp, Paul (October 20–21, 1885). "Ernst Laas. (Nekrolog)". Allgemeine Zeitung, no. 291 and 292. pp. 4289–4290, 4305–4307.
  2. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k Paul Kannengiesserm, "Ernst Laas." In Jahresbericht über die Fortschritte der classischen Alterthumswissenschaft. Biographisches Jahrbuch für Altertumskunde, ed. Iwan Müller, vol. 41, 123–136, Berlin: Verlag von S. Calvary & Co, 1885.
  3. ^ a b c d Dr. H. Holtzmann. "Worte am Grabe von Dr. Ernst Laas, Professor der Philosophie in Strassburg, gesprochen im Auftrage der Collegen von Professor" Viertel Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, edited by Richard Avenarius. pp. 1–6, Leipzig: Fues’s Verlag (R. Reisland). (1886).
  4. ^ a b c (1872). Die Pädagogik des Johannes Sturm historisch und kritisch beleuchtet. [A Historical and Critical Look at the Pedagogy of Johannes Sturm.] pp. iv-v, Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung.
  5. ^ Trendelenburg, Friedrich Adolf (1846). Historische Beiträge zur Philosophie. Berlin. pp. vii.
  6. ^ Laas, Ernst. Idealismus und Postivismus. Eine Kritische Auseinandersetzung. Erster, allgemeiner und grundlegender Theil. Vol. 1, Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung, 1879: 2, fn.
  7. ^ Lessing, Gotthold Ephraim. “Zeitung of June 29, 1751,” Sämmtliche Schriften, ed. Karl Lachmann. vol. 3, Berlin: Voss, 1838: 173. Link
  8. ^ Laas, Ernst (1887). Literarischer Nachlass. Vienna. pp. 5–6.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  9. ^ Laas, Ernst (1882). Idealismus und Postivismus. Eine Kritische Auseinandersetzung. Zweiter Theil: Idealistische und positivistische Ethik [Idealism and Postivism. A Critical Examination. Part Two: Idealist and Positivist Ethics] (in German). Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. p. 322.
  10. ^ Laas, Ernst (1887). Literarischer Nachlass. Vienna. pp. 7–8.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  11. ^ Köhnke, Klaus Christian, “Neukantianism zwischen Positivismus und Idealismus?,” in Kultur und Kulturwissenschaften um 1900: Idealismus und Positivismus, ed. Rüdiger vom Bruch, Friedrich Wilhelm Graf, and Gangolf Hübinge, vol. 2 (Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1997), 46. (Which in turn cites: Windelband to Karl Dilthey – Freiburg i.Br. 10 Aug. 1882, Nachlass of Karl Dilthey, Lower Saxony State and University Library Göttingen.).
  12. ^ Cf. G. König, Relativism, in: Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, ed. by Joachim Ritter and Karlfried Gründer, Vol. 8 (Darmstadt 1992) 613–622.
  13. ^ Köhnke, Klaus Christian (1997). "Neukantianism zwischen Positivismus und Idealismus?". Hübinger/Bruch/Graf (Eds.) Kultur und Kulturwissenschaften um 1900: Idealismus und Positivismus: 41–52.
  14. ^ Windelband to Georg Jellinek - Strasbourg i/E. March 22, 1883, Nachlass of Georg Jellinek, Federal Archives Koblenz, emphases by the Köhnke.
  15. ^ a b Curator of the University of Strasbourg to the State Secretary – Strasbourg 30/5 82. In: Köhnke, Klaus Christian, “Neukantianism zwischen Positivismus und Idealismus?,” in Kultur und Kulturwissenschaften um 1900: Idealismus und Positivismus, ed. Rüdiger vom Bruch, Friedrich Wilhelm Graf, and Gangolf Hübinge, vol. 2 (Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1997), 48.
  16. ^ Laas, Ernst (1884). "Ueber teleologischen Kriticismus". Viertel Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie: 1–17.
  17. ^ a b Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 665-666.
  18. ^ Cf. Ludwig Stein: Der soziale Optimismus (1905). Reprint Kessinger 2010, p. 178.
  19. ^ Rudolf Eisler (philosopher): Philosophen-Lexikon. Berlin 1912, pp. 371-373 (link).
  20. ^ Laas. In: Meyers Großes Konversations-Lexikon. 6th edition. Volume 12: L-Lyra. Bibliographisches Institut, Leipzig / Vienna 1908, pp. 2-3 (link).
  21. ^ Strasbourg-Koenigshoffen. Cimetière Saint-Gall (= Guide des cimetières n°2 de la Ville de Strasbourg). Strasbourg 2008, p. 59.
  22. ^ Hirschberger, Johannes (1966). Kleine Philosophiegeschichte [A Brief History of Philosophy] (in German) (6th ed.). Freiburg. p. 167.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  23. ^ Lehmann, Gerhard (1953). Geschichte der Philosophie [History of Philosophy] (in German). Vol. IX. Berlin. pp. 85–ff.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  24. ^ Kohn, Pinchas Jacob (1907). Der Positivismus von Ernst Laas. Inaugural-Dissertation der hohen philosophischen Fakultät der Universität zu Bern [The Positivism of Ernst Laas. Inaugural dissertation of the high philosophical faculty of the University of Bern] (in German). Bern: Cheitlin, Spring & Cie.
  25. ^ Laas, Ernst. Idealismus und Positivismus. Vol. I. p. 273.
  26. ^ a b Laas, Ernst. Idealismus und Positivismus. Vol. I. pp. 1-4.
  27. ^ Laas, Ernst. Idealismus und Positivismus. Vol. I. p. 4.
  28. ^ Cf. Lange’s (1873) Geschichte des Materialismus, Vol. I, 2nd ed., preface, pp. xxix–xxx. “But as I everywhere appealed to the sources... I hoped in this way to supply to a great extent the want of a proper monograph... This purpose consists now, as before, in the exposition of principles...”
  29. ^ Laas was particularly impressed with Mill’s Examination that thoroughly attacked and analyzed (for over 500 pages) Hamilton’s philosophy in order to damage his reputation. Cf. John Stuart Mill’s (1818) Autobiography, Mill's CW I, p. 270: “that the mere contrast of the two philosophies was not enough, that there ought to be a hand-to-hand fight between them, that controversial as well as expository writings were needed, and that the time was come when such controversy would be useful… As I advanced in my task, the damage to Sir W. Hamilton’s reputation became greater than I at first expected, through the almost incredible multitude of inconsistencies which shewed themselves on comparing different passages with one another.”
  30. ^ a b Trendelenburg, Friedrich Adolf (1855). "Ueber den letzten Unterschied der philosophischen Systeme". Historische Beiträge zur Philosophie. 2: 1–30.
  31. ^ Laas, Ernst. Idealismus und Positivismus. Vol. I. pp. 4–6.
  32. ^ Laas, IP1 22–3. Also see Laas, Ernst, “Neuere Untersuchungen über Protagoras,” ed. Richard Avenarius, Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie 8 (1884): 479–480. Indeed, for Laas, positivism meant the Protagorean and British Empiricist tradition, not Comte’s doctrine. This aligned with common German usage at the time. Cf. Lange, Friedrich Albert, Geschichte des Materialismus und Kritik seiner Bedeutung in der Gegenwart, 2nd ed., vol. 1, (Iserlohn: Baedeker, 1873): Ch. 2; Bratuscheck, Ernst, “Der Positivismus in der Wissenschaft,” ed. Ernst Bratuscheck, Philosophische Monatshefte 11 (1875): 49–64.
  33. ^ Laas, “Self-Advertisement for Idealism and Positivism. A Critical Examination. First, General and Foundational Part,” Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, 1879: 503.
  34. ^ Laas, IP1: 4.
  35. ^ a b c d e https://www.encyclopedia.com/humanities/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/laas-ernst-1837-1885 [bare URL]
  36. ^ Immanuel, Kant (1781–1787). Critique of Pure Reason.
  37. ^ Laas. Idealismus und Positivismus. Vol. I. pp. 69–73.
  38. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 72.
  39. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 15.
  40. ^ Cf. Ernst Laas: Kants Analogien der Erfahrung. Eine kritische Studie über die Grundlagen der theoretischen Philosophie. Weidmannsche Buchhandlung, Berlin 1876
  41. ^ (1882). Kants Stellung in der Geschichte des Konflikts zwischen Glauben und Wissen. Eine Studie. [Kant’s Role in the History of the Conflict Between Faith and Knowledge. A Study.] Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. Digitized.
  42. ^ See Pinchas Jacob Kohn: Inaugural-Dissertation der hohen philosophischen Fakultät der Universität zu Bern. Scheitlin, Spring & Cie., Bern 1907 (online in the Internet Archive).
  43. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 184.
  44. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 1-24. The introduction of the book spells out his aims and goals in a very clear manner.
  45. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 33-39.
  46. ^ See “Neuere Untersuchungen über Protagoras.” [“Recent Investigations into Protagoras”] In: Viertel Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, edited by Richard Avenarius, pp. 479–497, Leipzig: Fues’s Verlag (R. Reisland); and Natorp, Paul. Forschungen zur Geschichte des Erkenntnisproblems im Altertum: Protagoras, Demokrit, Epikur und die Skepsis, pp. 1-20, Berlin: Hertz, 1884. Reprint in Hildesheim: G. Olms, 1965. The debate sparked because Laas's PhD student Wilhelm Halbfass (Natorp likewise a PhD student of Laas) wrote his dissertation supporting Laas's position that Plato misreads and interprets Protagoras. Plato, as Halbfass claims, that "target Plato's portrayal and critique of the theoretical aspects of Protagoras's views in the Theaetetus." Forschungen zur Geschichte des Erkenntnisproblems im Altertum: Protagoras, Demokrit, Epikur und die Skepsis, pp. 1-4,
  47. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 37-38.
  48. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 44-46. All italics are by Laas.
  49. ^ a b Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 39-43 All the italics are to replicate Laas's writing.
  50. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 52-54.
  51. ^ a b Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 55-58.
  52. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 59-74.
  53. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 59-65.
  54. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 98-104. Also see Idealismus und Positivismus. §11–16. for a detailed analysis of each of these motifs.
  55. ^ IP1: §11–12.
  56. ^ IP1: 99-100
  57. ^ IP1: 126.
  58. ^ E.g. Laas is committed to logical realism. Cf. IP1: 255; and IP3: 255–56.
  59. ^ IP1: 183.
  60. ^ IP1: 222.
  61. ^ IP1: 188.
  62. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 2-5.
  63. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 5.
  64. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 230.
  65. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 8.
  66. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 232.
  67. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 12.
  68. ^ Laas occasionally referred to his publication as “sheets” [Blättern].
  69. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 272-275.
  70. ^ a b Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 179.
  71. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, pp. 178-183.
  72. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, pp. 178-179.
  73. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 182.
  74. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 43; 46.
  75. ^ Dragischa Gjurits (1871): Die Erkenntnistheorie des Ernst Laas. Eine Darstellung des Correlativismus. Inaugural-Dissertation zur Erlangung der philosophischen Doktorwürde. Oswald Schmidt, Leipzig 1902 p. 57. (online in the Internet Archive).
  76. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 45 f.
  77. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 47.
  78. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 48. The term experiential wholeness can be found in Felix Krueger: Zur Philosophie und Psychologie der Ganzheit. Berlin/Göttingen/Heidelberg 1953, p. 262. Krueger uses it to describe the "interaction of all experiential traits, including the after-effects of past ones, and [it] is rooted in the entire organism."
  79. ^ a b Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 48.
  80. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 178.
  81. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 181.
  82. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 35.
  83. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 17.
  84. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 51.
  85. ^ Dragischa Gjurits (1871): Die Erkenntnistheorie des Ernst Laas. Eine Darstellung des Correlativismus. Inaugural-Dissertation zur Erlangung der philosophischen Doktorwürde. Oswald Schmidt, Leipzig 1902 p. 60.
  86. ^ Ibid.
  87. ^ Cf. on Locke: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 63f; Richard Rorty: Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. pp. 149-166, ibs. p. 156; Wolfgang Röd: Der Weg der Philosophie. Munich 1996, pp. 63-66. Locke's successors, e.g. Berkeley and Hume, each followed this path in their own way.
  88. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume I, p. 58 f; 68 ff; 126 ff; and see Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 5; 314-318.
  89. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 438 f.
  90. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 459.
  91. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 2-6.
  92. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, pp. 10-14.
  93. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 30 ff.
  94. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 15 ff.
  95. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, pp. 19-22.
  96. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 24.
  97. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 25 ff.
  98. ^ Cf. David Hume: A Treatise of Human Nature I, Introduction, 4.
  99. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 30.
  100. ^ Dragischa Gjurits (1871): Die Erkenntnistheorie des Ernst Laas. Eine Darstellung des Correlativismus. Inaugural-Dissertation zur Erlangung der philosophischen Doktorwürde. Oswald Schmidt, Leipzig 1902 p. 14. (online in the Internet Archive).
  101. ^ Cf. Wilhelm Windelband: Lehrbuch der Geschichte der Philosophie. Tübingen 1912, 6th edition, p. 547.
  102. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 151, and Alexander Bain: Geist und Körper. Leipzig 1881, p. 52. Theories of knowledge also raised questions about the relationship between physiological and mental processes. Cf. pp. 1-5.
  103. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 151.
  104. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 53.
  105. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 36.
  106. ^ Cf. Kant: Critique of Pure Reason. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 63. In this context, the 1876 publication by Laas: Kants Analogien der Erfahrung is informative. Here Laas discusses the deficits of Kant’s philosophy and the completely different foundations of his positivist philosophy. Full text at archive.org
  107. ^ The 3rd follow-up to the Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung, published between 1874 and 1879. Jenaer Literaturzeitung.
  108. ^ C. Schaarschmidt: Rezension zu Ernst Laas: Kants Analogien der Erfahrung. Jenaer Literaturzeitung 1877, No. 5, p. 75. Link.
  109. ^ Compare. E.g. Heinrich Rickert: Der Gegenstand der Erkenntnis. Tübingen and Leipzig 1904, p. 125.
  110. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 229.
  111. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 98.
  112. ^ a b Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 293.
  113. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 224.
  114. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 109-113.
  115. ^ a b Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 117.
  116. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 142ff. Also see p. 52, note 5 and p. 102 note 3.
  117. ^ For the whole section, see Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, pp. 159-169.
  118. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 291.
  119. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 181f.
  120. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 182.
  121. ^ a b Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 207 ff.
  122. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 209.
  123. ^ a b Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 211-215.
  124. ^ Dragischa Gjurits (1871): Die Erkenntnistheorie des Ernst Laas. Eine Darstellung des Correlativismus. Inaugural-Dissertation zur Erlangung der philosophischen Doktorwürde. Oswald Schmidt, Leipzig 1902 pp. 10-20; 46 (online in the Internet Archive).
  125. ^ Cf. also Johannes Volkelt: Arthur Schopenhauer. 1923 op. cit. p. 89 ff.
  126. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 221.
  127. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 219 ff.
  128. ^ Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume II, p. 223.
  129. ^ Ernst Laas: Der deutsche Unterricht auf höheren Lehranstalten. Ein kritisch-organisatorischer Versuch. Weidmannsche Buchhandlung, Berlin 1872, p. VI. "How often had I sought it myself in the early days of my pedagogical work and sorely lacked it!"
  130. ^ Ernst Laas: Der deutsche Unterricht auf höheren Lehranstalten. Ein kritisch-organisatorischer Versuch. p. 4 f.
  131. ^ [1] Ernst Laas: Der deutsche Unterricht auf höheren Lehranstalten. Ein kritisch-organisatorischer Versuch. p. 25. “Latin has long since lost its dominant position over all modern languages… Latin has finally lost its place among scholars as well.”
  132. ^ Cf. Rudolf Lehmann: Der Deutsche Unterricht: eine Methodik für höhere Lehranstalten. Berlin 1897, reprint of the 3rd. Edition 1909, TP Verone Cyprus 2016, p. 107.
  133. ^ Ernst Laas: Der deutsche Unterricht auf höheren Lehranstalten. Ein kritisch-organisatorischer Versuch.
  134. ^ Cf. Ernst Laas: Kants Analogien der Erfahrung. Eine kritische Studie über die Grundlagen der theoretischen Philosophie. p. 255; and Cf. Laas: Idealismus und Positivismus. Volume III, p. 132.
  135. ^ Laas, Ernst (1879). Idealismus und Postivismus. Eine Kritische Auseinandersetzung. Erster, allgemeiner und grundlegender Theil [Idealism and Postivism. A Critical Examination. First, General and Fundamental Part.] (in German). Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung. pp. 1–5.
  136. ^ Chisholm 1911, p. 2.
  137. ^ Kannengiesser, Paul (1885). Müller, Iwan (ed.). "Ernst Laas". Biographisches Jahrbuch für Altertumskunde. Berlin: S. Calvary & Co: 123–136.

References

  •  This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domainChisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Laas, Ernst". Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 16 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 1–2. This work in turn cites:
    • Hanisch, Der Positivismus von Ernst Laas (1902)
    • Gjurits, Die Erkenntnistheorie des Ernst Laas (1903)
    • Falckenberg, Hist. of Mod. Philos. (Eng. trans., 1895)

All the biographic information for this article comes from three sources.

  1. Paul Natorp(October 20–21, 1885). "Ernst Laas. (Nekrolog)". Allgemeine Zeitung, no. 291 and 292. pp. 4289–4290, 4305–4307.
  2. Paul Kannengiesserm, "Ernst Laas." In Jahresbericht über die Fortschritte der classischen Alterthumswissenschaft. Biographisches Jahrbuch für Altertumskunde, ed. Iwan Müller, vol. 41, 123–136, Berlin: Verlag von S. Calvary & Co, 1885.
  3. Dr. H. Holtzmann. "Worte am Grabe von Dr. Ernst Laas, Professor der Philosophie in Strassburg, gesprochen im Auftrage der Collegen von Professor" Viertel Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, edited by Richard Avenarius. pp. 1–6, Leipzig: Fues’s Verlag (R. Reisland). (1886).