Exact sciences: Difference between revisions
King of the Changes (talk | contribs) m Added two references. Tag: Visual edit |
King of the Changes (talk | contribs) m Added two citations Tag: Visual edit |
||
Line 3: | Line 3: | ||
[[File:Ulugh Beg's Astronomic Observatory.jpg|thumb|upright|[[Ulugh Beg]]'s [[meridian arc]] for precise astronomical measurements (15th c.)]] |
[[File:Ulugh Beg's Astronomic Observatory.jpg|thumb|upright|[[Ulugh Beg]]'s [[meridian arc]] for precise astronomical measurements (15th c.)]] |
||
The '''exact sciences''', sometimes called the '''exact mathematical sciences''',<ref name = "Grant_43">{{Citation | last = Grant | first = Edward | author-link = Edward Grant | date = 2007 | title = A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century | publisher = Cambridge University Press | place = Cambridge | page = 43 | isbn = 9781139461092 }}</ref> are those sciences "which admit of absolute precision in their results"; especially the [[mathematical sciences]].<ref>{{ Citation | title = Oxford English Dictionary, Online version | edition = 2nd | date = June 2016 | contribution = Exact, ''adj.<sup>1</sup>'' | publisher = Oxford University Press | place = Oxford }}</ref> Examples of the exact sciences are mathematics, [[optics]], [[astronomy]], and [[physics]], which many philosophers from [[Descartes]], [[Leibniz]], and [[Kant]] to the [[Logical positivism|logical positivists]] took as paradigms of rational and [[Objectivity (philosophy)|objective knowledge]].<ref>{{Citation | last = Friedman | first = Michael | author-link = Michael Friedman (philosopher) | editor-last = Earman | editor-first = John | editor-link = John Earman | date = 1992 | title = Inference, Explanation, and Other Frustrations: Essays in the Philosophy of Science | contribution = Philosophy and the Exact Sciences: Logical Positivism as a Case Study | series = Pittsburgh series in philosophy and history of science | volume = 14 | page = 84 | publisher = University of California Press | place = Berkeley and Los Angeles | isbn = 9780520075771}}</ref> These sciences have been practiced in many cultures from antiquity<ref>{{Citation | last = Neugebauer | first = Otto | author-link = Otto Neugebauer | date = 1962 | title = The Exact Sciences in Antiquity | publisher = Harper & Bros. | place = New York | edition = 2nd, reprint | series = The Science Library }}</ref><ref>{{Citation | last = Sarkar | first = Benoy Kumar | author-link = Benoy Kumar Sarkar | date = 1918 | title = Hindu Achievements in Exact Science: A Study in the History of Scientific Development | publisher = Longmans, Green and Company | isbn = 9780598626806 | place = London / New York | url = https://books.google.com/books?id=1CpRAAAAYAAJ }}</ref> to modern times.<ref>{{Citation | last1 = Harman | first1 = Peter M. | last2 = Shapiro | first2 = Alan E. | date = 2002 | title = The Investigation of Difficult Things: Essays on Newton and the History of the Exact Sciences in Honour of D. T. Whiteside | publisher = Cambridge University Press | place = Cambridge | isbn = 9780521892667 }}</ref><ref>{{Citation | last = Pyenson | first = Lewis | date = 1993 | title = Cultural Imperialism and Exact Sciences Revisited | journal = Isis | volume = 84 | issue = 1 | pages = 103–108 | doi = 10.1086/356376| quote = [M]any of the exact sciences… between [[Claudius Ptolemy]] and [[Tycho Brahe]] were in a common register, whether studied in the diverse parts of the Islamic world, in India, in Christian Europe, in China, or apparently in Mesoamerica. | jstor = 235556 | bibcode = 1993Isis...84..103P | s2cid = 144588820 }}</ref> Given their ties to mathematics, the exact sciences are characterized by accurate [[Quantitative research|quantitative]] expression, precise predictions and/or [[rigour|rigorous]] methods of testing [[hypothesis|hypotheses]] involving quantifiable [[prediction]]s and [[measurement]]s<ref>{{Cite book |last=Shapin |first=Steven |title=The Scientific Revolution |publisher=The University of Chicago Press |year=2018 |isbn=9780226398341 |edition=2nd |location=Chicago, IL |pages=46-47 |language=}}</ref>. |
The '''exact sciences''', sometimes called the '''exact mathematical sciences''',<ref name = "Grant_43">{{Citation | last = Grant | first = Edward | author-link = Edward Grant | date = 2007 | title = A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century | publisher = Cambridge University Press | place = Cambridge | page = 43 | isbn = 9781139461092 }}</ref> are those sciences "which admit of absolute precision in their results"; especially the [[mathematical sciences]].<ref>{{ Citation | title = Oxford English Dictionary, Online version | edition = 2nd | date = June 2016 | contribution = Exact, ''adj.<sup>1</sup>'' | publisher = Oxford University Press | place = Oxford }}</ref> Examples of the exact sciences are mathematics, [[optics]], [[astronomy]]<ref>{{Cite book |last=Drake |first=Stillman |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.3138/j.ctvcj2wt5 |title=Essays on Galileo and the History and Philosophy of Science: Volume 1 |last2=Swerdlow |first2=N.M. |last3=Levere |first3=T.H. |date=1999 |publisher=University of Toronto Press |isbn=978-0-8020-7585-7 |doi=10.3138/j.ctvcj2wt5}}</ref>, and [[physics]], which many philosophers from [[Descartes]], [[Leibniz]], and [[Kant]] to the [[Logical positivism|logical positivists]] took as paradigms of rational and [[Objectivity (philosophy)|objective knowledge]].<ref>{{Citation | last = Friedman | first = Michael | author-link = Michael Friedman (philosopher) | editor-last = Earman | editor-first = John | editor-link = John Earman | date = 1992 | title = Inference, Explanation, and Other Frustrations: Essays in the Philosophy of Science | contribution = Philosophy and the Exact Sciences: Logical Positivism as a Case Study | series = Pittsburgh series in philosophy and history of science | volume = 14 | page = 84 | publisher = University of California Press | place = Berkeley and Los Angeles | isbn = 9780520075771}}</ref> These sciences have been practiced in many cultures from antiquity<ref>{{Citation | last = Neugebauer | first = Otto | author-link = Otto Neugebauer | date = 1962 | title = The Exact Sciences in Antiquity | publisher = Harper & Bros. | place = New York | edition = 2nd, reprint | series = The Science Library }}</ref><ref>{{Citation | last = Sarkar | first = Benoy Kumar | author-link = Benoy Kumar Sarkar | date = 1918 | title = Hindu Achievements in Exact Science: A Study in the History of Scientific Development | publisher = Longmans, Green and Company | isbn = 9780598626806 | place = London / New York | url = https://books.google.com/books?id=1CpRAAAAYAAJ }}</ref> to modern times.<ref>{{Citation | last1 = Harman | first1 = Peter M. | last2 = Shapiro | first2 = Alan E. | date = 2002 | title = The Investigation of Difficult Things: Essays on Newton and the History of the Exact Sciences in Honour of D. T. Whiteside | publisher = Cambridge University Press | place = Cambridge | isbn = 9780521892667 }}</ref><ref>{{Citation | last = Pyenson | first = Lewis | date = 1993 | title = Cultural Imperialism and Exact Sciences Revisited | journal = Isis | volume = 84 | issue = 1 | pages = 103–108 | doi = 10.1086/356376| quote = [M]any of the exact sciences… between [[Claudius Ptolemy]] and [[Tycho Brahe]] were in a common register, whether studied in the diverse parts of the Islamic world, in India, in Christian Europe, in China, or apparently in Mesoamerica. | jstor = 235556 | bibcode = 1993Isis...84..103P | s2cid = 144588820 }}</ref> Given their ties to mathematics, the exact sciences are characterized by accurate [[Quantitative research|quantitative]] expression, precise predictions and/or [[rigour|rigorous]] methods of testing [[hypothesis|hypotheses]] involving quantifiable [[prediction]]s and [[measurement]]s<ref>{{Cite book |last=Shapin |first=Steven |title=The Scientific Revolution |publisher=The University of Chicago Press |year=2018 |isbn=9780226398341 |edition=2nd |location=Chicago, IL |pages=46-47 |language=}}</ref>. |
||
The distinction between the quantitative exact sciences and those sciences that deal with the causes of things is due to [[Aristotle]], who distinguished mathematics from [[natural philosophy]]<ref>{{Cite book |last=Principe |first=Lawrence |title=The Scientific Revolution: A Very Short Introduction |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2011 |isbn=9780199567416 |location=New York, NY |pages=27}}</ref> and considered the exact sciences to be the "more natural of the branches of mathematics."<ref name = "Grant_42">{{Citation | last = Grant | first = Edward | author-link = Edward Grant | date = 2007 | title = A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century | publisher = Cambridge University Press | place = Cambridge | pages = 42–43 | isbn = 9781139461092 }}</ref> [[Thomas Aquinas]] employed this distinction when he said that astronomy explains the [[Figure of the Earth|spherical shape of the Earth]] by mathematical reasoning while physics explains it by [[material cause]]s.<ref>{{Citation | last = Aquinas | first = Thomas | author-link = Thomas Aquinas | title = Summa Theologica | at = Part I, Q. 1, Art. 1, Reply 2 | url = http://www.newadvent.org/summa/1001.htm#1 | access-date = 3 September 2016 | quote = For the astronomer and the physicist both may prove the same conclusion: that the earth, for instance, is round: the astronomer by means of mathematics (i.e. abstracting from matter), but the physicist by means of matter itself. }}</ref> This distinction was widely, but not universally, accepted until the [[scientific revolution]] of the 17th century.<ref name = "Grant_303">{{Citation | last = Grant | first = Edward | author-link = Edward Grant | date = 2007 | title = A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century | publisher = Cambridge University Press | place = Cambridge | pages = 303–305 | isbn = 9781139461092 }}</ref> [[Edward Grant]] has proposed that a fundamental change leading to the new sciences was the unification of the exact sciences and physics by [[Kepler]], [[Isaac Newton|Newton]], and others, which resulted in a quantitative investigation of the physical causes of natural phenomena.<ref name = "Grant_312">{{Citation | last = Grant | first = Edward | author-link = Edward Grant | date = 2007 | title = A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century | publisher = Cambridge University Press | place = Cambridge | pages = 303, 312–313 | isbn = 9781139461092 }}</ref> |
The distinction between the quantitative exact sciences and those sciences that deal with the causes of things is due to [[Aristotle]], who distinguished mathematics from [[natural philosophy]]<ref>{{Cite book |last=Principe |first=Lawrence |title=The Scientific Revolution: A Very Short Introduction |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2011 |isbn=9780199567416 |location=New York, NY |pages=27}}</ref> and considered the exact sciences to be the "more natural of the branches of mathematics."<ref name = "Grant_42">{{Citation | last = Grant | first = Edward | author-link = Edward Grant | date = 2007 | title = A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century | publisher = Cambridge University Press | place = Cambridge | pages = 42–43 | isbn = 9781139461092 }}</ref> [[Thomas Aquinas]] employed this distinction when he said that astronomy explains the [[Figure of the Earth|spherical shape of the Earth]]<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Cormack |first=Lesley |date=1994 |title=Flat Earth or round sphere: misconceptions of the shape of the Earth and the fifteenth-century transformation of the world. |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/44251730 |journal=Ecumene |volume=1 |issue=4 |pages=365 |via=JSTOR}}</ref> by mathematical reasoning while physics explains it by [[material cause]]s.<ref>{{Citation | last = Aquinas | first = Thomas | author-link = Thomas Aquinas | title = Summa Theologica | at = Part I, Q. 1, Art. 1, Reply 2 | url = http://www.newadvent.org/summa/1001.htm#1 | access-date = 3 September 2016 | quote = For the astronomer and the physicist both may prove the same conclusion: that the earth, for instance, is round: the astronomer by means of mathematics (i.e. abstracting from matter), but the physicist by means of matter itself. }}</ref> This distinction was widely, but not universally, accepted until the [[scientific revolution]] of the 17th century.<ref name = "Grant_303">{{Citation | last = Grant | first = Edward | author-link = Edward Grant | date = 2007 | title = A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century | publisher = Cambridge University Press | place = Cambridge | pages = 303–305 | isbn = 9781139461092 }}</ref> [[Edward Grant]] has proposed that a fundamental change leading to the new sciences was the unification of the exact sciences and physics by [[Kepler]], [[Isaac Newton|Newton]], and others, which resulted in a quantitative investigation of the physical causes of natural phenomena.<ref name = "Grant_312">{{Citation | last = Grant | first = Edward | author-link = Edward Grant | date = 2007 | title = A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century | publisher = Cambridge University Press | place = Cambridge | pages = 303, 312–313 | isbn = 9781139461092 }}</ref> |
||
[[Linguistics]] and [[comparative philology]] have also been considered exact sciences, most notably by [[Benjamin Whorf]].<ref>Benjamin Whorf, Linguistics as an exact science. In <i>Language, thought and reality: Selected writings of Benjamin Lee Whorf.</i> Edited by J.B. CarrollM.I.T. Press, 1956, 20–232.</ref> |
[[Linguistics]] and [[comparative philology]] have also been considered exact sciences, most notably by [[Benjamin Whorf]].<ref>Benjamin Whorf, Linguistics as an exact science. In <i>Language, thought and reality: Selected writings of Benjamin Lee Whorf.</i> Edited by J.B. CarrollM.I.T. Press, 1956, 20–232.</ref> |
Revision as of 00:54, 11 September 2023

The exact sciences, sometimes called the exact mathematical sciences,[1] are those sciences "which admit of absolute precision in their results"; especially the mathematical sciences.[2] Examples of the exact sciences are mathematics, optics, astronomy[3], and physics, which many philosophers from Descartes, Leibniz, and Kant to the logical positivists took as paradigms of rational and objective knowledge.[4] These sciences have been practiced in many cultures from antiquity[5][6] to modern times.[7][8] Given their ties to mathematics, the exact sciences are characterized by accurate quantitative expression, precise predictions and/or rigorous methods of testing hypotheses involving quantifiable predictions and measurements[9].
The distinction between the quantitative exact sciences and those sciences that deal with the causes of things is due to Aristotle, who distinguished mathematics from natural philosophy[10] and considered the exact sciences to be the "more natural of the branches of mathematics."[11] Thomas Aquinas employed this distinction when he said that astronomy explains the spherical shape of the Earth[12] by mathematical reasoning while physics explains it by material causes.[13] This distinction was widely, but not universally, accepted until the scientific revolution of the 17th century.[14] Edward Grant has proposed that a fundamental change leading to the new sciences was the unification of the exact sciences and physics by Kepler, Newton, and others, which resulted in a quantitative investigation of the physical causes of natural phenomena.[15]
Linguistics and comparative philology have also been considered exact sciences, most notably by Benjamin Whorf.[16]
See also
References
- ^ Grant, Edward (2007), A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 43, ISBN 9781139461092
- ^ "Exact, adj.1", Oxford English Dictionary, Online version (2nd ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, June 2016
- ^ Drake, Stillman; Swerdlow, N.M.; Levere, T.H. (1999). Essays on Galileo and the History and Philosophy of Science: Volume 1. University of Toronto Press. doi:10.3138/j.ctvcj2wt5. ISBN 978-0-8020-7585-7.
- ^ Friedman, Michael (1992), "Philosophy and the Exact Sciences: Logical Positivism as a Case Study", in Earman, John (ed.), Inference, Explanation, and Other Frustrations: Essays in the Philosophy of Science, Pittsburgh series in philosophy and history of science, vol. 14, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, p. 84, ISBN 9780520075771
- ^ Neugebauer, Otto (1962), The Exact Sciences in Antiquity, The Science Library (2nd, reprint ed.), New York: Harper & Bros.
- ^ Sarkar, Benoy Kumar (1918), Hindu Achievements in Exact Science: A Study in the History of Scientific Development, London / New York: Longmans, Green and Company, ISBN 9780598626806
- ^ Harman, Peter M.; Shapiro, Alan E. (2002), The Investigation of Difficult Things: Essays on Newton and the History of the Exact Sciences in Honour of D. T. Whiteside, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ISBN 9780521892667
- ^ Pyenson, Lewis (1993), "Cultural Imperialism and Exact Sciences Revisited", Isis, 84 (1): 103–108, Bibcode:1993Isis...84..103P, doi:10.1086/356376, JSTOR 235556, S2CID 144588820,
[M]any of the exact sciences… between Claudius Ptolemy and Tycho Brahe were in a common register, whether studied in the diverse parts of the Islamic world, in India, in Christian Europe, in China, or apparently in Mesoamerica.
- ^ Shapin, Steven (2018). The Scientific Revolution (2nd ed.). Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. pp. 46–47. ISBN 9780226398341.
- ^ Principe, Lawrence (2011). The Scientific Revolution: A Very Short Introduction. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. p. 27. ISBN 9780199567416.
- ^ Grant, Edward (2007), A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 42–43, ISBN 9781139461092
- ^ Cormack, Lesley (1994). "Flat Earth or round sphere: misconceptions of the shape of the Earth and the fifteenth-century transformation of the world". Ecumene. 1 (4): 365 – via JSTOR.
- ^ Aquinas, Thomas, Summa Theologica, Part I, Q. 1, Art. 1, Reply 2, retrieved 3 September 2016,
For the astronomer and the physicist both may prove the same conclusion: that the earth, for instance, is round: the astronomer by means of mathematics (i.e. abstracting from matter), but the physicist by means of matter itself.
- ^ Grant, Edward (2007), A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 303–305, ISBN 9781139461092
- ^ Grant, Edward (2007), A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 303, 312–313, ISBN 9781139461092
- ^ Benjamin Whorf, Linguistics as an exact science. In Language, thought and reality: Selected writings of Benjamin Lee Whorf. Edited by J.B. CarrollM.I.T. Press, 1956, 20–232.